We want to extend the notion of size of finite sets that is provided by the natural numbers so that we can compare the "size" of any two sets. It is worth noting that the following definition requires some reassurance that we are on mathematically firm ground since we are certainly on the edge of Russell territory. We will discuss this further when we consider alternatives to ZF set theory.
Let
be the equivalence relation on the "class" of all set defined by
setting
if there exists a 1 to 1 onto map
.
This is the books notation.
We define a second equivalence
relation
on the class of all set by
setting
if there exists a 1 to 1 map
and a 1 to 1 map
.
Finally, we
write
if the exist a 1 to 1
map
.
Exercise: Check that 1. and 2. are equivalence relations. For reference, you need to verify that
and
and
Observation:
For
and
its subsets, we have essentially shown, that
iff
We used this to also show that
Note
that if we only wanted to show that
,
it would have sufficed to present two one to one maps,
defined by
m,n
2
3
and
defined
by
m
m,1
Goals:
We show that, in general, for any pair of sets
iff
We also will show that for any pair of
sets,
or
First, the following useful theorem.
Let
be a partially ordered set in which every non-empty sub-set has a least upper
bound and a greatest lower bound. If
is order-preserving, that is
implies
,
then
has a fixed point (
).
Proof.
Before proceeding with the proof. We look at two examples:
Examples:
1.
- The map
n
n+1 has no fixed point. On the other hand,
,itself a subset, does not have a least upper bound.
2.
-
where,again,
,
and
,the usual ordering, on
and n
for
all
n
First, note that
satifies
the hypothesis of Tarski. To see this let
.
If
then it is the least upper bound (and the top element). If
and
is
finite then it, as a finite subset of
,
has a least upper bound( and again a top element). Finally, if
and
is
not finite,
is the least upper bound, in fact the only upper bound( but not the top
element)
Next, to see that the conclusion of Tarski holds, let
be order preserving. If
we have our fixed point. If
n
for some n then
,since
is
assumed to be order preserving.
Finally, an induction argument shows that, in general, any order preserving
map
has a fixed point.
Let
.
Then by definition,
.
Let
Since
,
is
non-empty. Hence
exists. For any
we have
and
,
so
is an upper bound for
. Thus
and
But, in general, if
then
because
implies
. Thus
and
Finally, we conclude that
.
For any pair of sets
iff
Proof.
By hypothesis, there exist one-to-one functions
and
.
We apply the Fixed Point Lemma to the poset
and the function
where
.
Here the exponent
signifies Set complement.
Note that
is order-preserving
Hence, by the Tarski Fixed Point
Theorem, there is a set
such that
Specifically
,
We can now define a 1 to 1 onto map
by
,
and
for
.
9.3.1 Lemma: In the setting of the Proof of
9.3
, the union being disjoint.
Proof.
That the union is disjoint simply follows from the fact that
.
In addition, since
is one to one we also can write
, with
. Intersecting both sides with
gives
But
and thus
or, taking the complements of both sides
9.3.2 Theorem:
In the setting of the Proof of 9.3,
then
,
where
Moreover
the union is a disjoint union of non empty sets.
Proof.
From 9.3.1
That the sets are disjoint follows from the fact that
and
,
hence
,are one to one
We are now about ready to move to a more general discussion of set theory and
cardinals. We begin by noting that a more general discussion is appropriate by
showing that there are other cardinalities to be considered other than that of
and its finite subsets .
For any set
,there is no onto map
.
Proof A:( yet another diagonal argument. This is just Russell's argument in a non-paradoxical setting)
Let
.
Since
is onto there is some
with
.
As usual, by definition if
then
and if
then
.
Proof B:( yet another diagonal argument. This is just a disguised version of A.)
Let
0,1
.
Let
be the set of all maps from
to
. There is an obvious 1 to 1 onto map
Specifically,
1
. Hence to prove 9.4 we can show that for any set
,there is no onto map
.
Suppose there was such a map. Define
by the formula
The
rest of the proof is standard. Suppose there was some
such that
Compute
If
0
then by definition
1
and so on.....
Proof C:( yet another fixed point theorem. )
We first prove the following lemma, which is really a generalization of B.
9.4.1 Lemma : For sets
and
, suppose
there exists an onto map
,
then every self-map
has
a fixed point.
Proof:
Consider the "evaluation" map
defined by the formula
Like in B, above define
by the formula
Again, since
is onto there is some
such that
We have
on the other hand, by definition,
Thus
is a fixed point for
Now, to complete the proof of 9.4, Let
0,1
and note that
has a fixed point free self-map. In particular, let
be define by the formula
0
1
and
1
0
.
Notation:
The standard notation for
is
.
For
,
if
is a set with
we use multiplicative notation
for
Check that this is well defined.
If
is a set with
,
the standard notation for
is
,
as suggested by the second proof of 9.2 .
The standard notation for
is
We will be very interested in
We end this Page with a Theorem that is in fact a special case of a general
result about infinite cardinals.
Proof:
Let
and
be the odd and even natural numbers respectively. In full detail,
.
Again, letting
0,1
We invoke Lemma a. on the Background Page to observe
that there is a one-one onto map.
Hence,
Let
be a finite set with
,
then
Hint:
Use Lemma 0.3 b. on the Background Page and
9.4 above to prove the theorem by induction for
2
.
Next use 9.3 to prove the result when
22
Solution
One verifies that
2
and
2
By induction, suppose we have shown that
The map
is one to one and onto.
Similarly
is one to one and onto.
Thus
is one to one and onto.
Now assume
22
and choose one to one maps
and
These
induce one to one maps.
and
Finally, apply Schroder-Bernstein to
and
.