12. Well Ordered Sets

12.1 Theorem:

Let $\QTR{Large}{A}$ be Well Ordered

  1. If MATH n then $\QTR{Large}{A}$ is order isomorphic to $\QTR{Large}{n}$.

    or

  2. $\QTR{Large}{A\ }$is order isomorphic to MATH

    or

  3. For some MATH,MATHis order isomorphic to MATH.

Proof:

  1. By induction, if MATH 1 then the Theorem is immediate. Suppose the result holds for MATH n-1. Let MATH be the top element. The is an order isomorphism MATHExtend $\QTR{Large}{f}$ to $\QTR{Large}{n}$ by setting $\QTR{Large}{f(}$n$\QTR{Large}{)=t}$.

  2. Again, by induction, one shows that for n MATH there a unique MATH such thatMATHn. Hence by 1. one has order isomorphisms MATH. Checking that MATH we have an order isomorphism MATH. Either MATH.

    or

  3. MATH where $\QTR{Large}{a\ } $is the least element of MATH



In more generality.

12.2 Theorem:

Let $\QTR{Large}{A}$ be Well Ordered then the only self-order isomorphism MATH is the identity map.

Proof:

Suppose $\QTR{Large}{f}$ is not the identity map. Let $\QTR{Large}{s}$ be the least member of $\QTR{Large}{A}$ such that MATH .

The segment mapping formula tell us that MATH

but by assumption MATH hence MATHand thus by 11.1.1 MATH

12.2 Corollary:

Let $\QTR{Large}{A}$ and $\QTR{Large}{B}$ be Well Ordered and order isomorphic then the order isomorphism MATH is unique.

MATH

Let MATH be two order isomorphisms. MATH is a self-order isomorphism, hence the identity map, MATH. Thus MATH.


12.3 Theorem:

Let $\QTR{Large}{A}$ be Well Ordered and let MATH ,$\ $ there is no order isomorphism MATH.

Proof:

Suppose there was an order isomorphism MATH

Since MATH there exists some $\QTR{Large}{s<a}$ such that MATH In particular MATH

Let MATH. Since $\QTR{Large}{A[a]}$ is Well Ordered let MATH

Thus MATH $\QTR{Large}{[l]}$ is the identity map. Restated MATH MATH $\QTR{Large}{[l].}$But

MATH MATH MATH MATH . Thus MATH, contradicting the definition of $\QTR{Large}{l}$ .


12.4 Lemma:

Let $\QTR{Large}{A}$ be Well Ordered. Let MATH be an Ideal Cut, then $\QTR{Large}{I=A}$ or for some , MATH , MATH

Proof:

If MATH, let MATH

12.5 Theorem:

Let $\QTR{Large}{A\ }$and $\QTR{Large}{B}$ be Well Ordered then

  1. $\QTR{Large}{A}$ is order isomorphic to a segment of $\QTR{Large}{B}$.

    or

  2. $\QTR{Large}{B\ }$is order isomorphic to a segment of $\QTR{Large}{A}$.

    or

  3. $\QTR{Large}{A}$ and$\QTR{Large}{\ B\ }$are order isomorphic.

Proof:

Notes and Observations

Consider the Set of triples MATH where MATH and MATH are Ideal Cuts and, MATH is an order isomorphism.

We let MATH MATH if

Exercise(due Wed. March 29) Show that this is an ordered Set. (Hint: use 12.2).

Assuming this, Consider the triple MATH where MATH. Again, one checks that this is an order isomorphism.

Clearly the triple is maximal with respect to the three bullets. In particular, MATH and MATH are Ideal Cuts (11.1.2). Thus by 12.4 , MATH, MATH or both are segments and we can then extend $\QTR{Large}{f,}$ a contradiction.


On the next Page we will want a "constructive" version of the material just presented. In particular, we will extract Well Ordered subsets of posets. Here are the details.

We are given a poset MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$. We restrict attention to MATH , the Well Ordered subsets.

Definition 12.6:

A subset MATH is called "complete" if MATH and MATH implies

MATH . That is if a Well Ordered subset is in MATH so are all its segments. Clearly MATH itself is complete.

Note: Implicit in the definition is the assumption that MATH is Well Ordered, "vacuously".

If you are uncomfortable with this assumption, just define "complete" on MATH .

Note: One also finds these subsets called "good" or "special."

Theorem 12.7:

Fix MATH Let MATH be the set of Well Ordered subsets with least element MATH Let MATH be complete and such that there exists a function MATH with the property that MATH for all MATH and MATH then MATH MATH.

Proof:

One needs to show that to show that if MATH and MATH are in MATH then MATH, MATH for some MATH , or MATH for some MATH.

As we noted before, in that case, MATH is Well Ordered

Let MATHbe the set of common Ideal Cuts of MATH and MATH . From the hypothesis

MATHis not empty. Hence MATH is common Ideal Cut of MATH and MATH . Hence MATH or MATH or both, or $\QTR{Large}{I}$ is a segment of both. But, suppose

there exists MATH and MATH such that MATH .

But MATH a contradiction since then MATH would be a common Ideal Cut.

Examples:

1. For MATH, let MATH2. Let MATH $\QTR{Large}{\{}$finite sequences of all even numbers beginning with 2 and ending with 2n for some n$\QTR{Large}{\}.}$Clearly MATH is complete. Let $\QTR{Large}{F}$ MATH be any finite set. Define MATH Exercise Check that MATH satisfies the hypothesis of 12.7 for MATH Compute $\QTR{Large}{U.}$

2. MATH where MATH iff MATH and MATH. Let $\QTR{Large}{F}$ MATH be a chain. Define MATHExercise Find the appropriate MATH Compute $\QTR{Large}{U.}$



Ordinal Arithmetic

In discussing ordinal arithmetic it will be helpful to use a more precise notation for Well Ordered Sets.

12.8 Definition: Let MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$ and MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$ be two Well Ordered sets with , MATH MATH. We define a Well Ordering MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$ by the following three properties.

  1. MATH

  2. MATH

  3. MATH for MATH and MATH.

One checks

12.9 Theorem:

  1. Let MATH MATHbe well ordered with MATH n and MATH m, then, under the appropriate assumptions of disjointness, MATH is order isomorphic to MATH.

  2. Let MATH be order isomorphic to MATH , MATH be order isomorphic to MATH , MATH MATH, and MATH MATH, then MATHis order isomorphic to

MATH.

12.10 Observation:

As we have seen, in general, MATH is not order isomorphic to MATH

Look at MATHand MATH

12.11 Definition: Let MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$ and MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$ be two Well Ordered sets. We define a Well Ordering MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$ using "alphabetic order" as follows:

$\QTR{Large}{(s,t}$ MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

if

  1. MATH

    and if MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

  2. $\QTR{Large}{\ }$if MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

Exercise: Check that this is a Well Order (Due Wed. March 29)

12.12 Observation:

In general, MATH is not order isomorphic to MATH

Look at MATHand MATH

Exercise: How about $\QTR{Large}{(}$ MATH MATH

(Due Wed. March 29)

Solution:

The strategy is to write down the two definitions of order and observe that they are equivalent.

$\QTR{Large}{(}$ MATH

  1. ifMATH

    and if MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

  2. $\QTR{Large}{\ }$if MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

      1. if MATH

        and ifMATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

      2. if MATH

        and if MATH and MATH

    1. if MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

MATH

  1. $\QTR{Large}{\ }$if MATH

    and if MATH

  2. ifMATH

  1. ifMATH

    and if MATH

    1. if MATH

      and ifMATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$

    2. $\QTR{Large}{\ }$if MATH $\QTR{Large}{)}$