Responses to the Target Article in Style
"An Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Study"
Respondents
***************************************************************************************************
Art as Adaptation: A Challenge
Brian Boyd
University of Auckland
Joseph Carroll knows
literary Darwinism not only through breaking in the field but also from helping
so many newcomers over the fence, myself included. I agree with almost
everything he writes in the bulk of the article, but since we learn more from
disagreement, I will take issue with one section, The Adaptive Function of
Literature. Carroll’s account of my own proposal seems to me inaccurate, and
his own proposal seriously wanting.
I have proposed that
art is a human adaptation deriving from play, a widespread animal behavior.[1] Play
evolved through the advantages of flexibility, of behavior not fully programmed
genetically; the amount of play in a species correlates with its flexibility of
action. Behaviors like escape and pursuit, attack and defense and social
give-and-take can make life-or-death differences. Creatures with more
motivation to practice such behaviors in situations of low urgency on average
fare better at moments of high urgency. Animals that play repeatedly and
exuberantly hone skills, widen repertoires and sharpen sensitivities. Play
therefore has evolved to be highly self-rewarding. Because it is compulsive,
animals engage in it again and again, incrementally altering muscle tone and
neural wiring, strengthening and speeding up synaptic pathways, improving their
capacity and performance.
Humans uniquely inhabit “the cognitive
niche” (Tooby and De Vore). We therefore have an appetite for information, and
especially for pattern, information that falls into meaningful arrays that
allow rich inferences. Like other species, humans can assimilate information
through the rapid processing that specialized pattern recognition allows, but
unlike other species we also seek, shape and share information in open-ended
ways. We actively pursue the patterns that make data swiftly intelligible,
especially those yielding the richest inferences in our core information
systems, the senses of sight and sound, and our most crucial domain, social
information.
Art is a kind of
cognitive play with pattern. Just as play refines behavioral options over time
by being self-rewarding, so art serves as a playground in which the mind
increases cognitive skills, repertoires and sensitivities. Like play, art
succeeds by engaging and rewarding attention, since the more focused our
attention and the more frequent and intense our response the more powerful the
neural consequences.[2]
Art’s appeal to our preferences for pattern means that we expose ourselves to high
concentrations of humanly appropriate information eagerly enough so that over
time we strengthen the neural pathways that process key patterns in open-ended
ways.
Other functions follow
from this. Individuals who can earn the attention of others through art gain in
status. Emotional attunement in cognitively appealing forms improves social
cohesion, as does the creation of engaging prosocial models. Fiction can create
scenarios for reasoning about action in ways that earn attention, emotion and
recall. Art can be appropriated by religion, to intensify traditions and social
commitments, but it can also foster creativity, especially in large communities
with high specialization of labor. Carroll critiques creativity as if it were
the prime function I propose for art, when in my account it comes in fifth, and
explicitly only because the other functions are already in place.
I find it hard to
understand Carroll’s proposal, so let me quote what I take to be his core
claims: art “organiz[es] motivational systems disconnected from the immediate
promptings of instinct. . . . The proliferation of possibilities in ‘mental
scenarios’ detached from instinct produces a potential chaos in organizing
motives and regulating behavior. The arts produce images of the world and of
our experience of the world. Those images mediate our behavior and the
elemental passions that derive from human life history.” Carroll rests much of
his case on an appeal to the authority of E. O. Wilson, but Wilson—whom I
admire on this side idolatry—offers little evidence for his claims.
Carroll rightly
approves Tinbergen’s famous four questions about any adaptation: where does it
come from? (phylogeny); how does it develop? (ontogeny); what is it for?
(ultimate function); how does it work? (mechanism or proximate function). Let
us apply these criteria to his cognitive order proposal and my cognitive play
proposal.
Phylogeny: Following Wilson, Carroll
proposes a sharp discontinuity between the “instinct-driven” behavior of other
animals and the human “proliferation of possibilities in ‘mental scenarios’
detached from instinct.” Modern ethologists who focus on animal cognition argue
with much convincing evidence for deliberate, reflective strategizing in
chimpanzees, orangutans, dogs, wolves, dolphins, and corvids. Chimpanzees have
been found to outdo humans on at least one evolutionarily novel cognitive task.[3] We
and capuchin monkeys alike have a visceral sense of fairness: we will choose to
reject an offer, even at our own expense, if we deem it unfairly divided. Is
this only instinct for a capuchin but something more for us?
For the purpose of
this argument at least, Carroll stresses only human exceptionalism, a sharp
phylogenetic break, a rise above instinct into a massive mental proliferation
of scenarios of possible action. He provides no evidence to show that humans
regularly decide to act by selecting from “a prodigious and constantly updated
library of scenarios” (Swirski 74, building on Wilson, cited by Carroll). We
can indeed concoct scenarios but rarely have the time to fashion them in detail
on the fly and test the network of forking if/then outcomes. We produce
scenarios only serially, and therefore slowly, in the highly constricted space
of working memory. It takes time to develop them, time we rarely have in the
heat of the moment. Elsewhere Carroll rightly praises literature as a major
repository of human self-knowledge. Odysseus, the most intelligent of Greek
heroes, stops himself in Polyphemos’s cave because he can run one scenario
forward and see that if he kills Polyphemos then they will all be
trapped behind the boulder only the Cyclops can move. It takes even Odysseus
hours to work out one other scenario that he indeed executes
successfully. Homer has it right: human minds can inhibit automatic reactions
better than other animals, through the enlarged prefrontal cortex (for
inhibition, specifically, especially the orbitofrontal cortex), but they cannot
generate and evaluate under pressure large number of scenarios involving ramifying
if-then calculations. Our minds can form options, when allowed time, but they
remain simple and even one we may choose to follow tends to become irrelevant
as other parties react unpredictably.
A sharp phylogenetic
break between action driven by instinct and action chosen through the
production and selection of options from a Borgesian library of possibilities
seems contrary to the evidence of both ethology and cognitive neuroscience. But
because Carroll supposes such a break, he also proposes, with Wilson, “a
potential chaos in organizing motives and regulating behavior.” Art, which he
claims exists to solve this alleged and evolutionarily unprecedented problem,
therefore has no evolutionary precursors. Bird and whalesong, with their
dialects and fashions, elaborate gibbon duetting, the creation of visual
displays by bowerbirds, dolphins or chimpanzees: these are automatically
excluded from any prospect of continuity with human art.
The
cognitive play proposal by contrast derives art from play, already
self-motivating across many animal classes and perhaps universal in mammals;
from our intense curiosity (an attribute developing among the higher primates),
and the intense appetite we have for rich and therefore patterned information;
and from the unique human pressure for social attunement[4]
(another attribute developing along the primate line), especially between
parent and child, and leading therefore, to the patterned play of
protoconversation as a start for art.[5]
Ontogeny:
Carroll refers to Dissanayake on protoconversation, and to Tooby and Cosmides’s
“Does Beauty Build . . . ,” although not to their stress there on childhood,
but he seems to have little interest in the individual development of art. The
potential chaos in “organizing motives and regulating behavior” that comes from
a proliferation of scenarios seems to be a problem he envisages adults facing
and needing art to solve.
The
cognitive play proposal by contrast stresses the development of art in the
individual, since we can see emerging capacities there in detail and through
experiment in ways we cannot in the phylogenetic record. With Dissanayake, I
see protoconversation, with its play with rhythmic, harmonic, melodic and
kinetic patterns, as an important evolved scaffolding for the further
elaboration of pattern that infants engage in as they learn to sing, dance,
draw or shape and especially as they engage in pretend play. Infant behavior
seems not to arise out of a need to cope with over-proliferating scenarios.
Rather, pretend play amplifies their capacity to generate scenarios, but
scenarios that engage attention through unusual characters and actions—a duck
confronting a dinosaur, dragons poo-pooing on rooftops until the houses
collapse. Children learn to fashion short simple vivid scenarios first in
action, with the physical props at hand, including each other, and then without
action props but with the cultural props of received story elements like
dragons and fairies. But the evidence of childhood storymaking suggests it has much
more to do with play and engaging intense attention than with constructing
scenarios for non-play action.
Function: The
cognitive order proposal sees the function of art as compensating for a
hypothesized motivational disorganization arising from a hypothesized
over-proliferation of mental scenarios, for neither of which independent
evidence is offered. Even supposing art did have this function, how would it
work? Carroll suggests that the images of art “mediate our behavior and the
elemental passions that derive from human life history.” “Mediate” could hardly
be more vague. How does the invention of the piccolo or of a new pigment like
ultramarine “mediate” our behavior, control (if it does) our over-proliferation
of scenarios, organize our motivation? I can see how either would attract
attention and therefore invite engagement with the art in which it features, in
a world where habituation threatens any mere repetition of stimuli, but I
cannot understand how a piccolo or a pigment might “mediate” our alleged
motivational disorganization.
My cognitive play
hypothesis proposes a series of functions, beginning with the core function of
strengthening neural pathways through the intense repeat engagement that the
play of art invites, in the patterns that matter most to us—especially, in
story, patterns of agency and action—so that we can more readily produce and
especially process patterns in those modes. Evidence of neural growth as a
consequence of play in rats is already at hand.[6]
Animals trained or raised in enriched environments increase brain weight “by 5
per cent in the cerebral cortex . . . and up to 9 per cent in areas that the
training directly stimulates” compared with genetically identical animals in
impoverished environments (Doidge 43). We cannot experimentally impoverish
human children, but the human predisposition for art has ensured for tens of
thousands of years that we grow up in especially enriched environments. Since
we cannot dissect the brains of human experimental subjects and cannot yet
easily investigate single neurons in live human minds, we rely on animal
evidence. This shows that training makes discrimination finer, processing
faster and signals clearer, provided the animals pay close attention and
provided training occurs in increments (Doidge 67, 155).
Art depends on
attention, and its capacity to command attention means that just as with play
we are motivated to engage in it again and again. Neuroscience has yet to show
the long-term effects of visual art and storytelling on the brain, but in at
least one art, music, there is already robust evidence for improved pattern
detection in those who have had even some training.[7] In a
highly social species inhabiting the cognitive niche, any gain in mental
processing in our key modes, especially, in the case of narrative, in
interpreting social events and managing multiple representations, offers a
competitive advantage. And any gain in the ability to attune one’s feelings to
others and to motivate such attunement, in a situation where multilevel
selection operates—as it has repeatedly done in human evolution[8]—offers
a competitive advantage against other groups. Think work songs, battle songs,
anthems, hymns, heroic stories.
Mechanism:
Carroll does not explain the proximate mechanisms that would make people engage
in art as he conceives it. Formulations like “Modern humans cannot choose not
to live in and through their own imaginative structures” do not even begin to
point to a mechanism. If people over-proliferate scenarios and therefore suffer
motivational disorganization, how do they know to make an elaborate headdress
or paint a still life, or to sing or dance or tell stories as the way to help
them? Help them do what, in any case? Reduce the number of scenarios? (Won’t
more stories increase the number of scenarios?) Select the appropriate scenario
to act on? How does a Bach fugue or the Beatles’ “Blackbird” help here—and how
do we know which to choose?
The cognitive play
proposal suggests a number of motivational mechanisms. The key motivational
neurotransmitter, dopamine, is elevated at the onset of and during play, and
that same reward factor presumably helps motivate protoconversation, pretend
play, and the playfulness of any inventive art. We know humans have strong
preferences for high-yield, high-pattern information over informational chaos.
We know of the strong human status drive, and its correlation with attention;
individuals particularly motivated to seek status and attention in artistic
ways can therefore design their work in order to maximize the
attention-engaging power of their art. We have a strong drive to imitate
others, which enables us to acquire at least the rudiments of local artistic
traditions. We have a pleasure in mastery, when we dance or sing or make visual
designs or tell stories, and partly by way of mirror neurons we can feel the
effort and estimate the mastery involved in others’ craft. We have a uniquely
intense motivation to attune ourselves to others,[9] and
song, dance and story fine-tune and amplify our capacity for attunement.
Carroll claims that in order decisively to falsify his or Wilson’s hypothesis, one would have to demonstrate that human cognitive evolution had simply stopped at some point in the past. He seems closer here to immunizing the hypothesis from falsification than inviting it to genuine test. And his proposal seems to me, in Pauli’s terms, “not even wrong.” Various phases of my hypothesis, on the other hand, would be falsified, for instance, if repeat engagement in particular arts were shown not to improve the processing of information patterns in the relevant cognitive modes, or if there were on average a negative correlation between artistic success and individual status, or if there were on average a negative correlation between the artistic richness of societies and independent measures of social cohesiveness. I offer phylogeny, ontogeny, a series of functions and suggestions toward mechanisms. Joseph Carroll’s contribution to the field of literature and evolution has been immense, not least in this magisterial survey, but I am not sure what he offers here on the adaptive value of art and literature except the authority of E.O. Wilson.
*************************************************************************************************************************
University of Tennessee
Some personal reflections
Joseph Carroll is a leader in the movement
to bring evolutionary analysis into the humanities and literary criticism in
particular. Not only did he write the first major monograph this area (Evolution
and Literary Theory), but he has immersed himself in the original writings
of Charles Darwin and edited a volume of his major writings. Indeed, he has
avoided the sometimes bowdlerized and narrow takes of many evolutionary
psychologists, anthropologists, and sociobiologists to evolution and Darwin
himself. In this target article, the depth of Carroll’s understanding and
familiarity with the biological areas of psychology combined with his inclusion
of recent scholarly contributions to literary and broadly humanistic
applications of evolutionary approaches, both pro and con, is very impressive.
I am not a literary scholar nor a
human-focused evolutionist or psychologist. My love and interests go more to
watching non-human animals in the field and studying their behavior in the
laboratory. This field is greatly devoted to Charles Darwin.[10]
(Burghardt, “Darwin’s Enduring Legacy”). But for me, as for Carroll, all
behavior is of a piece, and as we slice and dice and specialize, it all must
come together again. Many ethologists and biologists have written about the
origin and development of art, such as Desmond Morris, Dale Guthrie, Jocelyn
Crane, Eibl-Eibesfeldt, and Wolfgang Wickler.[11]
Music is gaining recent attention as well. Early human history and nonhuman
premonitions of art and music are increasingly able to be reconstructed based
on archeology, anthropology, and study of living nonhuman animals. However,
literature has remained the most resistant, since it is dependent on both the
development of writing and its preservation. We have no ability to know the
stories passed on orally, with the possible exception of preliterate art that
may have some narrative thrust. It is thus understandable that those humanistic
and historical disciplines dependent on the written word have had little use for
evolution until recently. Besides, their adherents may claim, since writing is
such a recent innovation in human history, evolution probably has little to do
with it. Here I will make some general comments on the issues discussed by
Carroll, the status of cross-disciplinary evolutionary thinking derived from my
experience, and comment on the research program that he advocates.
Joseph Carroll visited the University of
Tennessee some years ago after I had organized an interdisciplinary colloquy on
Evolution and Culture. This colloquy grew out of a luncheon talk I gave to a
large group of faculty interested in interdisciplinary outreach at the
university. The talk was on the promise and perils of the ‘new’ evolutionary
psychology. The resulting colloquy lasted for a number of years involving
professors from English, sociology, economics, history, psychology, philosophy,
classics, biology, computer science, modern languages, law, political science,
and anthropology. After several invigorating years, our university
administration had a call for interdepartmental research/training proposals.
Our proposal to formalize our bottoms-up faculty initiative with significant
funding for courses, visiting fellows, and graduate students was summarily
rejected as nothing new! What I also discovered is that for all their general
interest in evolution, suspicions of a real incorporation of
evolutionary thinking into their fields were a threat to many faculty members,
even the sympathetic. Although we began with a noted evolutionary biologist at
UT giving a primer on levels of selection and a series of other presentations
on evolution and Darwinism, for too many evolution was, at most, just one more
perspective to be added to their field, as Carroll notes. Suspicions of
evolutionary hegemony, social darwinism, genetic determinism, quantitative
science, and the sensationalist claims made in popular books and magazines were
too strong. In retrospect, the old view that revolutions take place through
replacing the graybeards, resistant to accepting ideas that seem to put their
entire intellectual life at risk, should have been realized. Even young
traditional scholars in the social sciences and humanities have, until
recently, been exposed to little serious evolutionary or even scientific
thinking. And biologists have not helped either. E. O. Wilson’s strident
reductionism and ‘we will bury you’ rhetoric should have been expected to raise
red flags. The politically motivated resistance of S. J. Gould, Lewontin, and
others to accepting that evolutionary processes have any direct effect on our
behavior seemed to give scientific credence to an old-fashioned behavioristic
environmentalism. Many of the first phalanx of self- proclaimed evolutionary
psychologists and journalists quickly produced heavily marketed popular books,
longer on adaptationist plausibility than solid evidence, and this disturbed
psychologists and evolutionary biologists alike. Perhaps this is why, after an
initial flutter of interest, most evolutionary biologists at UT avoided serious
involvement in the colloquy as well, seeming to view it as a bit too discursive
and unscientific.
Ironically, one of the problems is that E.
O. Wilson and others make the strong and very old-fashioned claim that animals
are motivated by instinct and humans by rational thought. I hear here the echo
of Descartes and the more modern scholastics such as Adler (The Difference
of Man). If, as Carroll claims, cognitive psychology and neuroscience are
essential resources for literary Darwinism, then it may be relevant to
incorporate some of growing literature on the cognitive and emotional
expressiveness of nonhuman species, episodic memory (necessary for narrative),
theory of mind debates, proto-language, etc. (for example, Terrace and
Metcalf). Furthermore, emotion and motivation are all closely tied to
biological processes and have certainly been incorporated in discussions of
instinct.[12]
During the ‘instinct wars’ of the 1950s and
1960s, set off by Nobel Laureate Niko Tinbergen in The Study of Instinct,
many useful refinements were made and incorporated into our understanding of
the development of species-typical behavior. Indeed, terms such as instinct and
innate are now far more commonly used in mainline studies in behavior and
neuroscience than was imaginable in 1970. But we also now appreciate more fully
that innate or instinctive mechanisms underlie even much learned and cultural
behavior, from what we fear to what we like to eat to how we fight, love, and
play. There is a heritability and individual difference factor to how we
process experiences, and there is no reason that this cannot be reflected in
literary analysis beyond the bland assertion that animals are instinct machines
and we are not (of course the related ideas of nature versus nature have been a
stock ploy of much literature including Caliban in The Tempest and the
novels of Thomas Hardy). Just as we can find roots of morality in our primate
relations (de Waal) so may we find roots of narrative and discourse. The last
thing we want to do is return to Cartesian dualism, and I sometimes fear that
in an attempt to show how special we are in terms of social life, culture, and
the arts we are prone to accept bad science that accords with our
anthropocentric ‘instincts.’ It is difficult to ignore our relationship with
other species at the same time arguing that the same selective processes
operating in solving similar recurrent themes underlie our behavior.
Some recent books, not cited by Carroll
(for example, Buller), explicitly critique many of the founding examples in the
field of evolutionary psychology. As in the instinct wars, these will
ultimately fail in their major purpose of derailing the field, but may put it
in on a firmer track with a richer destination. Carroll may want to address
these critics (including Panksepp and Panksepp, whom he does cite) as well as
those on the literary side. Sometimes wars have many fronts to be held for
ultimate victory.
The Tinbergen tradition
One of the possible weaknesses of literary
Darwinism is the neglect of earlier evolutionary approaches to psychology.
Ethology was a field started to incorporate a more truly comparative approach
to animal and human behavior. The term ‘ethological psychology’ pre-dated
modern evolutionary psychology.[13]
Ethology as I define it is “the naturalistic study of behavior from an
evolutionary perspective” (Burghardt, The Genesis 10). It builds on
Tinbergen’s famous four aims of all behavior study (Tinbergen, “On the Aims”):
the study of causal mechanisms (stimuli, hormones, and neural mechanisms),
development, adaptive value (or function), and evolution (both pattern and
process). Tinbergen was himself very uncomfortable with issues of subjectivity,
questioning even the study of play behavior, perhaps a result of his struggle
to wrest the ‘objective study of behavior’ from remnant Dutch vitalists in the
1930s and 1940s. Be that as it may, I added as a fifth aim, critical for the
future of ethology, that of ‘private experience,’ broadly conceived (“Amending
Tinbergen”). In any event, it seems to me that losing an integrative
perspective has held back both a rigorously empirical evolutionary psychology,
and associated branches that are only now be rectified. Note that traditional
experimental psychology was based primarily on the first two of Tinbergen’s
aims. Classical ethology reinvigorated the evolutionary aim, but empirical
studies of adaptiveness were rare. Tinbergen himself reinvigorated that aspect
of ethology. With the advent of the writings and conceptual advances of Hamilton,
Trivers, E. O. Wilson, Maynard Smith, Dawkins, and others, use of genetic
models and selfish gene thinking became incorporated into a revitalized study
of adaptiveness. This bore fruit largely due to a combination of new methods
including computerized behavior recording and model testing, developments in
tracking individual animals in captive and field settings, and especially the
advent of DNA methods to assess individual identity and paternity in the field.
A second critical development was the renewed interest in sexual selection that
grew out of the volume marking the 100th anniversary of the
publication of Darwin’s seminal tome The Descent of Man, and Selection in
Relation to Sex (1871). Thus, while the earliest ‘modern’ evolutionary
psychologists, largely ignored individual differences (for example, Barkow,
Cosmides, and Tooby), sexual differences were not, and the earliest
applications of evolutionary thinking to literature and myth involved sexual
selection logic. The initial focus on some almost mythical, but vaguely dated,
EEA (Environment of Evolutionary Adaptiveness) may have been an useful conceit
early on, but the premise that there was some ‘golden age’ in which natural
selection shaped our social and cognitive traits more than any other time is
not creditable (for example, Panksepp and Panksepp). Carroll is stimulating
when he discusses the need to incorporate life history, human universals, and
the recurring problems endemic to all human lives regardless of culture.
My point is that it is essential to look at
literature and all other human endeavors through all 5 aims to obtain genuinely
useful understanding of human nature and the evolutionary background involved.
By doing so we can, in effect, incorporate much of value from related social
sciences and humanities while still working towards the inclusive vision put
forth by Darwin at the end of the Origin, as well as more recent comprehensive
visions such as Wilson’s Consilience. Carroll is clearly aware of these
issues, but I wonder why they were relegated to minor status. In short, Carroll
did not go far enough.
I share and resonate with the view that
evolutionary literary analysis should not shy away from the quantitative and
testable and go beyond the discursive. But I noted that there is no explicit
discussion in his paradigm of using quantitative phylogenetic methods in
tracking literary themes or cultural and historical mythology as has proved
useful in linguistics. As for development, in spite of the mention of
“developmental cognitive psychology” I see no formal incorporation of the
development of literary/story telling and story appreciation skills in children
from infants on. Major academic areas are devoted to children’s literature and
emergent literacy. Certainly insights can be gained from more formally
incorporating such understanding, especially at it relates to cultural, ethnic,
religious, social class, economic, and education backgrounds in how students
react to literature. Although Shakespeare is repeatedly mentioned, theatre is
largely ignored, as is film, science fiction, popular fiction, and other genres
that could be useful testing grounds for the generality of hypotheses.
Additionally, literary Darwinists seem
particularly fixated on the issue of the adaptive value of literature and the
arts. Certainly this is an interesting issue, and eventually may be critical,
but perhaps not as urgent as Pinker, E. O. Wilson, George Williams and other
might think. Consider play behavior. For years the major question asked was what
it was good for. With no convincing methods for determining this, scientists
largely lost interest in the topic in spite of its ubiquity in human and
nonhuman behavior. Consequently, in my recent book The Genesis of Animal
Play, I was as pains to look at the phenomenon from all five of the
ethological aims, not just one or two. I think any intellectual contribution
the volume will have is based on presenting an integrative view. In fact, I
argue that fixating on adaptiveness held back serious scientific attention to
play as constituting important and fascinating phenomena. I think the long-term
success of literary Darwinism is tied to encouraging multiple rigorously
applied paradigms to the study of literature, broadly conceived.
In spite of any critical points above (and the ignorance on which they
may be based), I think that Joseph Carroll’s essay is a true example of
productive and integrative scholarship.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Brett Cooke
Texas A&M
From the evidence
offered in Carroll’s target article, we can say that Darwinian Literary Studies
(DLS) have come of age. Once Ellen Dissanayake (What Is Art For?, Homo
Aestheticus) demonstrated the presence of “making special,” a feature
salient to natural selection, in works of art of all cultures, all periods, it
seemed evident, at least to a few of us, that all artistic media would be
encompassed in a paradigm like that described by Carroll. Looking back over the
past three decades, from Dissanayake’s first article on art and ritual
(“Hypothesis”), it seems obvious that the time was ripe. Until the mid-nineties
the nascent field was characterized by something like “convergent evolution,”
as investigators working independently arrived at similar conclusions.
Carroll’s Evolution and Literary Theory (1995) had a profound impact and
became a rallying point for the field. It set out a large-scale theoretical
program and helped isolated researchers realize that they were part of a
collective effort. Carroll has continued to play a major role in this effort
both by pursuing his own individual research and by repeatedly surveying and
critiquing the field as a whole. The target essay makes bold and sweeping
claims. Some readers might understandably quail at the prospect of an
all-encompassing, apparently monolithic, critical perspective conveyed in often
alien language and suggesting, perhaps, an air of arrogant intellectual
superiority. I strongly support the general program described by Carroll, but I
think some qualifications and modulations could help promote wider acceptance.
The chief promise of DLS lies in its
potential to explain what I term differential interest. The central
function of any viable modern work of art is to attract our attention. Some do
this better than others, indeed, repeatedly, possibly for predictable reasons.
Darwinian scholars often cite the universality of themes related to genetic
issues readily adducible to genetic influences. Although literary fashions
change, some subjects are virtually ubiquitous, while others are rarely, if
ever encountered. Incest avoidance, romantic love, birth defects, interpersonal
justice, and other issues of adaptive significance not only are universal, but
appear to elicit nearly inexhaustible attention. Ancient environments are often
reflected in modern literature. Albeit snakes are now a minor threat, science
fiction continues to swarm with “Dracs,” much as folktales once teemed with
dragons.[14] The
same plots get written over and over again because we never tire of reading
them. Others are ignored. One exception derives from a wager: Chekhov’s story
about an ashtray.
A related feature is that these so-called
universals appear to elicit nearly inexhaustible interest. This is certainly a
feature of oral literature; however rich a given tradition, it is nevertheless
quite restricted by modern standards. Just the same, it presumably sufficed to
satisfy its host population over the course of entire lives. Inevitably this
meant rehearing the same tales several, possibly many times. Perhaps this is
why we find them so replete with universals, although, no doubt, other factors
are involved. Some of this same limitation may be perceived in other modern
narrative media shared by most Western cultures. The core opera repertory could
be said to number less than two hundred works. Yet more (or, literally, less),
full-length narrative ballet is dominated by the same six or seven pieces.[15] And
it may hold true for us, inasmuch as most scholars of modern literature reread
favorite classics with deepening satisfaction.
The relationship of
DLS to other critical perspectives is not necessarily hostile. One obvious
exception is the cultural constructivists’ complete refutation of genetic
influences on human behavior, a position increasingly untenable in the face of
recent behavioral science. But need we throw out the baby with the bath water?
Are there no valid findings of LitCrit that may find a welcome place in
Carroll’s paradigm? For example, consider the issue of bias, relevant to
deconstruction. Much of evolutionary psychology concerns how our cognition is
not a seamless, let alone faultless, general processor, but rather is
conditioned by ancestral (and relatively recent) history; we are somewhat
predisposed to select certain behavioral alternatives instead of others. There
may be common ground regarding the pervasive force of ideology, which may be
adduced to the needs of social bonding. After all, political theories like the
divine right of kings and fascism that now seem ridiculous to many of us once
held sway over large populations. Could this same penchant for gullibility
pertain to the hold fictions exert on us?
DLS promises to help us understand
super-stimuli or exaggeration. Compared to reality, works of art usually tend
to exaggerate the iterance or urgency of a biological issue. Much as male
peacocks exhibit outlandish tail feathers to catch the eyes of peahens, artists
make recourse to human “universals” to attract our attention. They may need to
exaggerate these common proclivities or, more likely, what triggers their
expression, if only to out-compete other artists who are doing likewise. Of
course, exaggeration may be counterposed with understatement, and so on, as
artists vie for our attention. Preliminary results suggest that Darwinist
tenets are easier to apply to narrative fiction than to actual human behavior,
perhaps for the same reason. I am presently finding more incest in War and
Peace than can be discerned in Tolstoy’s social environment. Utopian
fictions almost eerily conform to or reverse traditional patterns of human
nature, probably more than any actual society.[16] And
operas are, well, operatic.
Acceptance of the evolutionist paradigm by
the academic establishment also may depend, however, on how Darwinist scholars
address questions such as the following. My expectation is that some answers
will be found in the interconnection of evolutionary psychology and cognitive
studies (or at least, as Carroll describes it, its most proximate wing),
especially in so-called Theory of Mind.
How do we account
for individuality and unique texture? While Darwinist studies have often
emphasized proclivities found in most human societies, in other words, the
commonalities of literature, scholars are often attached to the peculiar
qualities of favorite, sometimes sui generis, texts. It stands to reason
that both universals and individual particulars are characteristics of any
literary classic, but some readers may think that Darwinians are answering the
question of lesser interest. How can we explain not just panhuman features,
often seen as evidence of a shared evolutionary history, but also unique
features? Furthermore, how can the same genome (individual writer) produce
hundreds of works, each bearing his or her individual stamp, but also each
somehow different from each other?
Perhaps much of this
can be adduced to social competition. Darwinism envisages a marketplace of
competing interests. Much as higher
species disseminate a great variety of genetic alternatives, the artistic
marketplace is one of a waxing array of ideas. Other avenues to this issue of
individuation and change are tied to the following two questions.
What is the
relationship between an artistic text and reality? Naively stated, does art
convey truth of some sort? Michelle Scalise Sugiyama advances the hypothesis
that a major source of aesthetic attraction to stories lies in the information
they impart (“Food”). This may work for traditional oral literature where
useful data regarding prey and predators are mentioned, sometimes featured. But
can this same thinking be applied to modern literature, let alone to abstract
forms of art, such as instrumental music? I suggest that it can, if
sufficiently abstracted beyond intended lessons to information about the
environment, especially human, that may be inferred from the text.
Literary historians are aware of instances where real world discoveries are
soon reflected in narrative, much as composers respond to the invention of new
instruments or artists to new technologies such as lead tubes for oil paint. This
also applies to new philosophical and psychological insights. Much of literary
sentimentalism can be attributed to the recognition that the lower classes had
sentiments similar in nature to those of the nobility. Indeed, literature can
readily be seen as playing an active role in what is, after all, a
co-evolutionary construct; culture is a means of accelerating biological
adaptation, which itself is a means of retaining increasingly refined
information. Scalise Sugiyama notes the vital insights modern narratives give
into interpersonal politics and personal subjectivity (“Reverse”).
Contemporaries often react to works of European literature as if they were
about real people. Since the major selection pressure on us derives from other
human beings, whereas we can learn to control most prey (often now livestock)
and predators (seemingly destined to survive only in zoos), this consideration
produces a model that yields unending competition and a consequent need for
ever more insight into human nature, the major topic of literature. I propose
that literature also serves to develop awareness of our own capabilities. Aesthetic
cognition, whereby art occasionally provides productive thinking, may
account for some of its appeal. In this may lie not only the satisfactions of
literary and plastic portraiture but even instrumental music and other
non-representational arts.
How can a largely
static genome account for the increasing dynamism of stylistic change?
Artistic history, if we look at the last few centuries, appears to be
accelerating. I suggest we can quite plausibly see this is due, in large part,
to the factors mentioned above: social competition amongst conspecifics,
responses to increasingly dynamic environments, and a waxing interest in
subjectivity. Style is more than mere form; to be viable it also needs to
reflect modes of thought, often newly recognized ones. Frequently stylistic
innovations are accompanied by novel insights, as in the case of Tolstoy’s
gestural language, Dostoevsky’s multileveled subjectivity, or Joyce’s
stream-of-consciousness.
What is the
Darwinian structure of a text? Probably, in a word, complex. Although
Darwinist studies of individual works often focus on one or a few vital tenets,
and the logic concerning a single strand may appear to be relatively simple,
this is not to say that these are not the only genetically-derived or –relevant
drives at hand. One reason that I published a book on utopian fiction (Human
Nature) was that I found that many different features of our evolved
psychology were relevant to a reading of Evgeny Zamyatin’s We, at least
nine in all. I have since drafted a tenth chapter and still sense that I have
only scratched the surface.
Moreover, genetic proclivities may
counterpose one another just as easily as they may be complementary. Much
aesthetic fascination may derive from the clash and/or choice of mutually
exclusive goods or evils. As in the case of Romeo and Juliet, the
internal structure may be agonistic, as we find in that play’s choice between
assortative mating (e. g., romantic love) and kin altruism (nepotism, family).[17] Many
parts of our genome express themselves in our physiology and behavior. Their
interaction, along with many environmental factors, greatly adds to our
individuation. Should we expect art to be any less complex? Potentially
everything about a classic text is subject to biocultural interpretation, and
it would be difficult to think of a feature in such a text that is not vital to
its aesthetic success. Much as I regard Joseph Carroll’s magisterial study of
Jane Austen’s Pride and Prejudice (Literary Darwinism) to be the
finest produced heretofore in the field, I am confident he agrees that his is
not the last word, that we may anticipate further Darwinian insights into this
novel.
Though
Darwinian Literary Studies have come of age, its agenda is hardly complete.
Tasks like those outlined above will fill out the picture of what it promises
for literary scholarship.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Frederick Crews
University of
California, Berkeley
When
Joseph Carroll’s Evolution and Literary Theory appeared in 1995, I read
the first hundred pages or so with great interest and took comfort from its
critique of the then poststructuralist-dominated literary academy. Carroll’s
presentation stood out for its comprehensiveness and its uncompromising embrace
of empirical values—the same values to which, since 1980, I myself had been
upholding against applied deconstruction and its ideologized progeny.[18] In
addition, I found that Carroll and I shared an intellectual hero, Charles
Darwin, who, for both of us, epitomized a determination to explain observed
effects only by reference to commonly ascertainable, temporally prior facts and
factors, without appeal to “final causes” and other such remnants of an
exhausted supernaturalism.
I
had no quarrel in 1995, and I have none now, with the central role that Carroll
assigned to Darwin’s theory of evolution for an explanatory overview of our
species. As I have recently stated, “Only a secular Darwinian perspective . . .
can make general sense of humankind and its works.”[19] But
whether that perspective ought to become the guiding philosophy of academic
literary studies is a different matter. That proposition struck me as lame when
I first encountered it, and the reasons now assembled by Carroll in its behalf
haven’t caused me to change my opinion.
Carroll’s
program is truly grand in intended scale. The literary Darwinians, he writes,
“aim at fundamentally altering the paradigm within which literary study is now
conducted.” Their goal is to “subsume all other possible approaches” to the
field. And if they succeed, that field’s current disrepute in empirical circles
will give way to admiration. By responsibly connecting literary analysis to
reliable knowledge about human nature and by making their own scrupulous
additions to such knowledge, critics will contribute to E. O. Wilson’s
consilience, helping to chart “an unbroken chain of material causation from the
lowest level of subatomic particles to the highest levels of cultural imagination.”
[20]
In
demurring from Carroll’s initiative, I do not mean to reject the realm of
theorizing to which his program appeals (sometimes rather sheepishly) for its
scientific backbone, evolutionary psychology. To be sure, that subdiscipline
has been plagued by a scarcity of hard evidence that might substantiate one
“Just-so Story” about emergent dispositions at the expense of rival hypotheses.
But this drawback may be mitigated someday by new sources of information, and
meanwhile there is much to be learned about cross-cultural regularities that
are suggestive of biological roots and adaptive functions in a broadly
Darwinian sense. That is why I agreed to contribute an encouraging foreword to
one of the cultural evolutionists’ most promising books, Jonathan Gottschall
and David Sloan Wilson’s anthology The Literary Animal.
The
chapters of that volume, along with most of the other studies that Carroll now
marshals as evidence of an incipient intellectual revolution, are
interdisciplinary efforts. Examining literary productions, from myths and fairy
tales through Shakespeare plays, they uncover motifs and narratological
patterns pointing to traits of general human nature. The results belong to
aesthetics, psychology, and anthropology, but not, as Carroll acknowledges, to
literary criticism, because the goal here is data extraction and replicable
social-scientific knowledge rather than identification and explanation of the
features that set a given work apart from others.
Nevertheless,
Carroll doesn’t hesitate to claim that critical analysis per se also ought to
take an explicitly Darwinian turn. Criticism, he holds, now suffers from a
“blank slate” neglect of biological and behavioral universals—a neglect
fostered on one side by impressionistic, idealizing, sentimentalizing humanists
and on another by poststructuralist obfuscators and ideologues. A Darwinian
outlook, in contrast, keeps a steady eye on “the urgent needs and driving
forces in life—survival, reproduction, kinship, social affiliation, dominance, aggression,
and the needs of the imagination.” And thus the Darwinian critic, starting from
the expected “life history” concerns of gendered authors, characters, and
readers, possesses an objective analytic baseline for showing how a given work
exemplifies, challenges, or complicates the norm. Such a critic, Carroll
maintains, can be fully sensitive to the work’s linguistic uniqueness without
neglecting “the world outside the text” and its more or less mimetic
representation.
To illustrate the difference that is made by
approaching a work from the angle of evolved human interests, Carroll has
elsewhere offered us sample analyses of well-known fictions, most notably Pride
and Prejudice. In his treatment, the demanding cognitive style of Jane
Austen, with its valuation of keen intellect and moral integrity, is shown to
work in fruitful tension with that novel’s raw life-history themes of “resource
acquisition and reproductive activity.”[21]
This sounds dry and diagrammatic, but in Carroll’s hands it is not; his discussion
faithfully recounts the structure and tone of Austen’s masterpiece. When
compared with recent academic practice, with its predetermined lessons about
patriarchy, class conflict, imperialism, desire, dialogism, and the
self-cancellation of the signified, that is distinctly refreshing.
Here
I must ask, however, whether this demonstration piece and others resembling it
can be generalized to warrant an overtly Darwinian emphasis in criticism at
large. Although Carroll derived his vantage on Pride and Prejudice from
evolutionary theory, all that was needed to arrive at the same emphasis was
open-minded attention. “Sex and property, family or kin relations, parenting,
social relations, and cognitive power” [22] are
Austen’s manifest concerns, largely forecast in her novel’s satirically playful
opening paragraph. Indeed, the very choice of a realistic novel about courtship
seems all too convenient on Carroll’s part. Would his “life history”
orientation be an equally good match for Beowulf, “Batter My Heart,
Three-Personed God,” A Tale of a Tub, Candide, “Kubla Khan,”
“There’s a Certain Slant of Light . . . ,” “Bateau Ivre,” “Jabberwocky,” “In a
Station of the Metro,” “Sweeney Agonistes,” “The Red Wheelbarrow,” “The Emperor
of Ice-Cream,” Six Characters in Search of an Author, Animal Farm,
Waiting for Godot, Dutchman, Rhinoceros, “Daddy,” The
Crying of Lot 49 . . . ?
The
question here is whether biologically grounded “human nature” themes and their
evolutionary background deserve a privileged status in particular critical
studies before we have even begun to find out where an author’s priorities lie.
Apparently so, in Carroll’s estimation. He expresses impatience with
traditionalist critics who “do not typically seek causal explanations in
evolutionary theory,” whereas Darwinians, he writes, “can identify the
biological forces that are invoked or repressed in any given work and can
assess how those forces impinge on meaning.” “Invoked or repressed”? Carroll’s
omnibus rejoinder will perhaps explain what he means here by repression and
whether he holds, with Derrideans and Lacanians, that the undetectability of a
favored “force” is really a sign of its imperfectly negated, and therefore
shaping, presence in the creating mind.[23]
Isn’t this the apriorism that Carroll decries in others?
In
rebuking colleagues who complain about reductive discourse, Carroll points out
that all explanatory efforts entail reduction. True enough. The pertinent
question, however, is whether much of anything is explained by reduction to the
most primordial level we can find, where perceived factors tend to be banal
common denominators that aren’t helpful for the particular instance. The logic
of inquiry would seem to require that we begin tackling a literary problem just
below the textual surface, where unified or divided intentions, biographical
experiences, psychological stresses, linguistic resources, traditions and
conventions, historical events, and social circumstances can all be seen to
have played a role. That is the normal practice of most critics, but it is
scarcely recognized, much less approved, in Carroll’s less than fair division
of the non-Darwinian literary professoriate into effete, allegorizing humanists
and madcap poststructuralists.
Although
he does attempt to promote his own school of literary criticism, Carroll has a
larger aim that requires a quite different strategy. In his opinion, students
of literature possessing a powerfully explanatory theory and a scrupulous
research protocol can unearth what he chooses to call “real knowledge,
knowledge that is consilient with the broader world of empirical research.”
Such lore consists not of aperçus about one work or another but of
universally valid truths about human propensities. The difference here is
crucial, because “the broader world of empirical research” won’t be impressed
by findings that fail to extend beyond, say, the time scheme of Othello
or the quaint theology of Paradise Lost. The rescue of literary study
from its current doldrums, Carroll feels, will be effected only if its
practitioners show that they, too, can cease being “passive consumers of
knowledge” and become, themselves, scientific investigators into human nature.
Accordingly, he recommends that literary academics be trained in statistical
analysis and other “empirical methods” borrowed from the social sciences.
Underlying
my several reservations about this program is an apparent disagreement with
Carroll on the meaning of empiricism—a pivotal term for both of us, but one
that points to different paths according to whether it is interpreted narrowly
or broadly. From Carroll’s manifesto I infer that he sees empiricism as the sum
of formalized procedures that, employing “the severe logic of quantitative
methodology,” can uncover verifiable patterns in structure or behavior. By that
definition, a critic who is accurately describing one text isn’t being fully
empirical. To count as such, our findings ought to be generalizable, couched in
numbers, procedurally controlled against bias and error, and preferably collaborative,
so that our neighbors in the flourishing sciences can trust them as meeting
their own standards of acceptability.
Judged
by these criteria, even Darwin would come under suspicion of having been a
third-rate empiricist. He worked and published alone, didn’t conduct
experiments, didn’t quantify his results, and was content to report his
impressions instead of laying out data that others could check. Yet we regard
the theory of natural selection as a triumph of scientific reasoning, because
later investigators who pressed that theory from every angle have found it to
be sturdy and indispensable. This suggests that empiricism resides not in any
methodological protocol but in all-around responsibility to evidence.
Such
responsibility, I would add, can be exercised in any nonaxiomatic field,
regardless of whether the knowledge in view is particular or general.
Empiricism entails setting aside partisanship and dogma, weighing the merits of
competing hypotheses, attending to objections and recalcitrant facts, and
wielding Ockham’s razor. Darwin did all that; but so, more modestly, does a
literary critic who is taking seriously the task of being as inductive and
circumspect as possible about analysis of a text.
The
subject matter of literary study is not human nature; it is literature. There
is nothing trivial about trying to make rich sense of single works, or single
careers, or single moments in literary history, that strike the common
understanding as representing a pinnacle of insight and skill. To imply
otherwise, as Carroll does in placing sorted and tabulated “real knowledge”
ahead of critical judgment, is to exemplify, not to rectify, the low valuation
of imaginative writing that is already depopulating our field while its
remaining exponents quarrel with one another over methodology. Moreover,
students who are still drawn to that field because certain poems and stories
have heightened their self-awareness and whetted their appetite for teaching
are left cold by charts, graphs, and tables. Carroll is proposing an
improvement that would induce them to stay away or drop out, further
constricting the already diminished lifeblood of our profession.
Many
literary critics and scholars, whether or not they make an occasional
perfunctory bow to some Continental guru, do earnestly observe empirical canons
in their work. That is, they conduct themselves as if they actually cared about
suiting their conclusions to the burden of available facts. Since the 1980s,
however, in the face of intimidation from the academic avant-garde, they have
been reluctant to speak openly about such “logocentric,” “positivistic,”
“epistemologically naïve” empiricism. But the intimidation appears to be easing
now that the top poststructuralist lawgivers, to whom few academics are listening
any longer, have reached their own nadir of bafflement and demoralization. This
would seem to be a propitious hour, not for advancing the interest of one
empirical school at the expense of others, but for urging a profession-wide
ethic whereby evidence is treated as the only legitimate arbiter between
competing theories and hypotheses.
A
consensus on that point would surely strike an outsider as uncontroversial and
hardly worth articulating. How else can one maintain a discipline than by
observing impersonal standards to which all parties are equally accountable?
But we who have watched “English” become the doormat of academic specialties
know that epistemic cynicism, identity politics, cliquish power plays, animus
against science, and a lax hospitality toward any theories that generate
abundant discourse have stifled objective judgment and even, in some quarters,
rendered it a term of abuse. [24]
Joseph
Carroll and I are in agreement about this state of affairs. We differ, however,
on what should be done about it. Carroll writes as the chief evangelist for a
single critical faction that comes near to claiming a monopoly on intellectual
seriousness, and he looks forward to a day when we will all pay homage to
Darwin as an earlier generation did to Foucault. In contrast, I believe in
affirming and rewarding what is already empirical in our field while standing
apart from factions and allowing intellectual give-and-take (as in this present
forum) to determine which current or forthcoming approaches to literature are
most cogent and comprehensive.
As I have suggested,
the biological and prehistoric emphasis of critical Darwinism makes for forced
or downright irrelevant application to most textual analysis. Instead of
conceding this limitation, Carroll draws instances from the most congenial
texts he can find, avoiding the harder cases that might test his ambitious
claims. Further, in a hermeneutic pirouette that would appear to border on
mysticism, he counts the “repression” of adaptationist factors—that is, their
failure to show up--as another form of presence. And then he proposes that
literary study expand its range, adopting social-scientific problems and
methods to which his Darwinian assumptions are, I grant, much better suited.
What lies behind all of these moves is loyalty not to the goal of open-ended
inquiry but to a theory that Carroll is bent upon exercising at all cost. When
he entreats his colleagues to be more empirical and invites their attention to
his own example, that partisanship is what they are likely to notice and
deplore.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Joseph Carroll is
essentially the founder and the preeminent theorist of Darwinian adaptationist
literary study, with an enviable mastery of the subjects relevant to his
interests: evolutionary theory (he has written a splendid monograph-length
introduction to his own edition of Darwin’s The Origin of Species) and
evolutionary psychology as well as an enormous amount of Western literature. In
addition, he understands statistics and can apply it in his own work; he is
also highly conversant with recent advances in cognitive science and
neuroscience. He is the obvious first choice to write a target article about
the emerging field that is called Literary Darwinism or Darwinian
(evolutionary, adaptationist) literary study and Style should be
commended for presenting to a broad audience this fertile and historically
inevitable approach. The curious, the convinced, the skeptical, and even the
hostile will be well repaid for their consideration of the article and the
commentary it provokes. The list of references is itself a compendium of
provocative recent thought about humans and their works (and workings).
Carroll makes an excellent
case for the necessity that scholars in the humanities and social sciences be
aware of the relevance of biology to their view of the human—what E. O. Wilson
has called “consilience.” It is a view that I wholeheartedly share. Participation
in and receptivity to the arts are demonstrably part of human nature, from
infancy (Dissanayake, “In the Beginning”), and the human mind, adapted for life
in the Pleistocene, is the source of all human thought and behavior. Today when
every educated person accepts that an individual human’s personality, talents,
susceptibility to disease, and indeed all other physical and psychological
traits are influenced by genes and DNA, it takes a very blinkered scholar
indeed to maintain that “cultural products” (inventions by humans, such as the
many different arts) appear willy nilly and can be about anything at all.
My addenda to
Carroll’s fine synthesis emerge from the rather different paths we have chosen
rather than from personal antagonism to his findings or conclusions. On the
contrary, I agree with him on just about every point. I suggest, however, that
there is additional evolutionarily-related knowledge that literary Darwinists
should consider. My own work uses a specifically ethological approach that is
concerned with artistic behavior more than with finished works
such as stories or novels or the qualitative features that make these
better or worse than each other. I deal with nonverbal arts, primarily music,
which in its origins and indeed today in many parts of the world would seem to
have included rhythmic movement or dance as part of the same activity. I view
all the arts as products of what I now call “artification”—that is, treating
ordinary objects, surroundings, sounds, movements, words, themes, motifs,
ideas, and so forth in specified ways that make them extra-ordinary. These
specified ways are the devices or “operations” on ordinary behavior that are
used instinctively by other animals in ritualized behaviors—formalization,
repetition, exaggeration, elaboration, and manipulation of expectation. Humans
use these intentionally or consciously to artify (or “make special”) their
experience. Evidence of this kind of behavior can be found as early as 100,000
years ago if not earlier. Bednarik finds evidence of artification as early as
900-200kya, if one accepts carefully carved cupules and incised lines on rocks
as examples of modifying objects and surroundings and red ochre fragments as
decorating the body. It is also likely that, like the arts in recent premodern
or traditional societies, early arts were participative and communal or, in the
case of petroglyphs and pictographs, the occasion for ritual/ceremonial
behavior. Artification is in my view a behavioral proclivity that--like
speaking, tool-using and making, and infant attachment—benefits all members of
a society, not only a talented few.
This is not the place
for a full exposition of my views about the evolution of the arts, but the
foregoing paragraph provides enough background for what I see as unaddressed
subject areas and perhaps problems for Darwinian literary study. (They are
problems for other schools of literary study too insofar as these ignore our
Pleistocene past and the lives of our hunter-gatherer ancestors whose way of
life over hundreds of thousands of generations molded our behavior and
emotions).
In my view, humans
were artifiers long before they were able to write and read, perhaps even
before they were able to speak or speak well. As Carroll points out, the
earliest literature would have been oral. I would suggest that there has not
been sufficient time for evolution to have acted specifically on reading as an
adaptation. Indeed, reading is a quite recent cognitive or behavioral
acquisition. It relies on the invention of writing in the Neolithic period, the
use of specifically alphabetic writing, and eventually the invention and
widespread use of the printing press. Literacy is a specialized skill and only
a small percent of all humans who have ever lived can read and even fewer read
fluently or for pleasure. Learning to read changes the brain and behavior of
individuals and the cultures they live in so that there are significant
differences between preliterate and literate individuals and societies (Ong;
Leavis; Wolf).
Reading, which is not
an adaptation, has obviously emerged from the human penchant (need?) for
listening to and telling stories, apparently a human universal. Reading
is a solitary act and listening/telling a social one. At the transition, people
gathered in a crowd to be read to (Leavis)—still a social experience, like the
participatory experiences in the arts that predominate in societies that have
not undergone the process of modernity.
The work by Gottschall
and others on cross-cultural and oral literature is welcome and I hope there
will be more. But there is something else to be learned about preliterate
literature than the way it reveals the human mind and its perennial concerns. Even
before (and alongside) the telling and hearing of stories, I think a case can
be made that our ancestors artified their voices and speech for incantations,
magical spells, lamentation—expressive verbal/vocalizations that make more or
less use of understandable words. That is, they may have intended to produce
musical (nonverbal) emotional effects more than to depict events with narrative
meaning. I suggest that a significant portion of our response even to
literature of today has to do with non-depictive or nonverbal aspects. In
poetry, it is not only the paraphrased “story” or even subject matter of the
poem (e.g., lost love, thoughts about dying, a sea voyage) that is memorable
and affecting. There are passages in literature and especially poetry—and
film--that have stunning or even indescribable-but-unforgettable emotional
residue that comes from image, sound, structure or unfolding in time, and
whatever can be suggested beyond words. This residue cannot be subsumed by
Basic Emotions theory.
One might say that
like Western classical music (also the product of musical literacy--a
first carefully composed and then published score that can be read and
performed by others), written literature is the product of people who can work
and rework their creations in order to make possible a kind of sophisticated
response in readers that goes beyond the fundamental human response to the
underlying elements of the story. Oral literature and improvised music have
their own significant rewards and can produce gripping or transfiguring
experiences—think of well-told tales and the music traditions of the Middle
East, South Asia, and East Asia—but the possibilities for manipulation of
emotion by published literature and music have provided new sorts of
appreciation in readers and listeners that are unavailable to oral, improvised
renderings. Concepts without distinct referents--“poetic truth,” the
“inexpressible”--are elements that some people value in novels by Woolf,
Proust, or Emily Bronte and in much poetry, as much as or more than the
fundamentals of the story. These have to do with the way in which the
story is presented. My own scheme of aesthetic operations—formalization,
repetition, exaggeration, repetition, and manipulation of expectation—does not
pin down the unpinnable, either, but I would like to see Literary Darwinists at
least acknowledge the aesthetic/emotional reward of this aspect of reading. and
locate its origin in affective (not purely cognitive) neuroscience. Cognitive
science makes much of symbolic representations, but in music it is the analogical
rather than symbolic meanings that carry affect. The arts, including
literature, also make important use of synaesthetic effects that engage all the
senses. Studies in affective neuroscience and in the cognitive
neuroscience of music might be a good place to look for models of how to
approach these less-traveled but important component of literary/artistic
response (for example, Malloch and Trevarthen; Panksepp, Affective).
Adaptationist literary
scholars should also remember that the experience of literature, like music,
may not be as aesthetically high-minded as I just described. Many people who
read do not read fiction (stories) and those who read fiction often read what
most of us who read Style would call CrapLit. People read fiction for
escape, titillation, vicarious adventure, and to kill time in an airplane or on
the beach. Nancy Pearl, a Seattle librarian, has written Book Lust and More
Book Lust, in which she recommends fiction for readers of varied tastes:
some primarily want a good plot, some historical sweep and atmosphere, some are
most interested in character: she presents nearly two hundred categories and
subcategories. Pearl’s readers seem to have distinct personality types. Where
do they fit into Carroll’s psychological scheme as readers? Are they
like the personality types of literary characters? Writers too would seem to
excel in one or another category. Carroll has mentioned character, setting, and
plot as constituting aspects of literary representations but these appeal
differentially to various sorts of readers or writers too.
I feel sure that
Professor Carroll would not disagree with most of what I say in this
commentary, which presents ideas that are of special interest to me. It is more
a matter of emphasis and personal predilection than of criticism or challenge. My
remarks are not meant to suggest inadequacies or deficiencies in the
superlative work done by Carroll and the other Literary Darwinists whom he
mentions. I bring them up here as interesting and relevant things to think
about and I hope that scholars who are attracted to the field might find them
worth considering in the future.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Joseph Carroll, the
doyen of Literary Darwinism, has convincingly portrayed the present (mainly
Anglo-American) state of the art in the application of evolutionary theory to
the analysis of literature. We do not have any objections against his very
instructive and well-balanced sketch, but we would like to point to some key
aspects which might follow out of the European tradition.[26]
Only few culturalists would
nowadays still deny the theory of evolution and its basic significance for the
explanation of human behavior; vice versa, only few biologically oriented
naturalists would still deny the significance of culture for the explanation of
human behavior. The communication difficulty rather seems to be that both sides
of the controversy, almost instinctively, immunize their reasoning against each
other by downsizing, or even ignoring, the significance of one component or the
other, so that the mutual acceptance frequently remains on the level of
formulaic lip services.
The controversy
between Joseph Carroll and Steven Pinker,[27] for
instance, in our eyes, reveals a typical case of underestimating the cultural
component. Its bone of contention has an old and dignified pre-Darwinian tradition:
“Aut prodesse volunt aut delectare poetae”—poets wish to either
instruct or to delight—as Horace writes in his Ars Poetica.
And he continues (this is quoted less frequently): “aut simul et iucunda et idonea dicere vitae”—or they wish to achieve both at the same time! We think
that the misleading alternative of either providing “pleasurable fantasies” or
fulfilling a “vital adaptive function”—that is, the explanation of art
as either a by-product or a distinct adaptation—could be dissolved in a similar
way: art can indeed be both, for it embraces a great range
of very heterogeneous activities. Moreover, as we shall argue in the following,
the pleasure we derive from art is particularly connected with the adaptive
value of art; whereas what is frequently assumed to be its adaptive
function—the production of “meaning,” as Carroll argues in the target article—seems
to us rather a cultural functionalization of the arts. But first
things first.
Carroll introduces
three criteria to determine the adaptive function of art: “(a) define art in a way that identifies what is
peculiar and essential to it—thus isolating the behavioral disposition in
question; (b) identify the adaptive problem this behavioral disposition would
have solved in ancestral environments; and (c) identify design features that
would efficiently have mediated the solution.” A
first difficulty is already apparent in the first criterion. “Art” is a concept
of ordinary language, precise enough if it is used in, and rendered monosemic
by, a particular conversational context; but is it useful as a starting point
for an evolutionary explanation? It would be more appropriate, perhaps, to
speak of the “arts” in the plural. To Pinker, an enthusiast of music, other
properties might be significant than to the literary scholar Carroll. But even
if we speak of the “arts” in the plural utterly diverse phenomena will be
subsumed in this term. Does fine arts embrace everything from Da Vinci to Duchamp?
Is literature everything from Hamlet to Donald Duck, and music
everything from Beethoven to digital ringtones? And if we also count the body
painting of the Huli people in Papua New Guinea, how about pierced teenagers in
Western societies? Every social environment produces its own ideas about “art.”
In fact, it would be no mistake to assume that those ideas, be they socially,
regionally or historically grounded, are cultural ideas. In every social
environment, then, diverse properties and functions are connected, in various
combinations and with various predominances: ‘purposiveness without purpose’, ‘making
special’, representation/depiction, play, religion, ‘handicap’, instruction,
emotional training, utopian imagination, mental health, and so on; and, of
course, sounds, colors, contours, words—all these are features and functions
which can occur in artifacts and aesthetic behavior—but they do not necessarily
have to.
However, there is no
need to give up the question for the evolutionary origins of the arts. On the
contrary, we should try to decompose what we today intuitively think art
to be into its fundamental elements, and then go back to the emergence of these
individual components in their respective EEA. This conforms with Carroll’s
second criterion that we must “identify the adaptive problem this behavioral
disposition would have solved in ancestral environments”—provided that we put
“problems” and “dispositions” into the plural. What is at stake is a multitude
of diverse adaptations, which were developed for a multitude of diverse
problems. And the procedure would have to be extended by yet another step. This
step is the analysis of the historico-cultural conditions and constraints which
determine that a specific combination of dispositions could establish itself,
and could perhaps even be employed to resolve new problems. Thus, the task
would be: (a) to decompose the everyday concept and phenomenon of “art” into
its fundamental elements, (b) to identify the evolutionary origins of these
components, and (c) to analyze the respective selection and higher-level
interplay of these components under diverse cultural circumstances.
This cannot be done
without a clear distinction between the original emergence of an adaptation on
the one hand, and its present form and function on the other hand, i.e.,
between the “ultimate” causation (the evolutionary origin) and the derived “proximate”
causation which persists through various cultural conditions.[28]
Concerning the proximate cause of aesthetic behavior, Pinker’s vote for
“pleasure” is, we think, an important contribution. In addition to that,
however, we would have to ask for the ultimate cause of that pleasure.
We would have to ask, in other words, why humans have evolved an intrinsic
motivation to activate their mental apparatus in non-functional contexts. On
this question, we regard the observations by Tooby and Cosmides in their essay
“Does Beauty Build Adapted Minds?” as seminal: They point out that “building
[such a complex machinery as the human] brain, and readying each of its
adaptations to perform its function as well as possible is [...] a vastly
underrated adaptive problem” itself (14). This problem was solved, they
believe, by evolving “aesthetic motivations” (i.e., ‘pleasure’ responses),
which help to “detect, seek, and experience certain aspects of the world,”
activate adaptive programs, and, by this means, serve as “a necessary guidance
system for the development of each adaptation” (15). Thus, seemingly pointless
behaviors do have an adaptive value, because those repeated performances in a
purely “organizational mode” (16) “help adaptations become organized into their
mature form” (15).[29]
From this perspective,
art behavior aligns with play behavior in animals and children as formerly
characterized by Karl Groos and Karl Bühler.[30] The
aesthetic preference systems detect appropriate occasions for play, that is,
they detect stimuli which are appropriate to trigger adaptive programs because
of an at least partial “isomorphism” (Tooby and Cosmides, “Does Beauty Build?”
16ff.) with selectionally relevant features of the EEA. Hence, the effects of
works of art have been compared to those of stimulus models.[31]
This comparison works especially well for several non-semantic aspects of the
arts. One can think of the many pointless repetitions which provoke endless
delight in little children and reoccur, as rhyme and verse, in poetry, as
melodic phrase in music, or as ornamental arabesques in painting (Eibl,
“Biologie”). One can further think of pre-semantic patterns of intensification
and decrease, or generally of all regular patterns and ‘gestalt’ forms which
normally guide our environmental experience and, in the organizational mode,
can be enjoyed as pleasurable principles of arrangement. Thus, even the
attendance at a symphonic concert is based, among others, on the pleasure which
already in the Pleistocene derived from pointlessly exercising and calibrating
our auditory system.
Stimulus model effects
also determine our emotional responses to the arts.[32]
This regards not only our more agreeable feelings, of which the phrase of the
famous “cheesecake for the mind” reminds us first, but also less agreeable
emotions like fear, sadness, or disgust. As the latter are equally adaptive
programs, their performance in the organizational mode is intrinsically rewarding
and can lead to such paradoxical phenomena as the ‘agreeable horror’ or the
‘joy of grief.’ However, unlike a bird, for instance, whose feeding activities
can be triggered by the open mouth of its offspring as well as by an
appropriate dummy, humans are able to “decouple”[33] the
sequence of information, drive and action, and to enjoy the triggered emotions without
the need for final reactions. Humans are not more “detached from instinct” than
any other animals (or even, ‘not “instinct-driven” at all’), as Carroll
paraphrases Wilson, but they are particularly capable of cognitively
controlling contingently true information by means of a specialized “scope
syntax,” [34]
of segmenting the triggered programs into individual subsequences, and creating
new combinations of them. Hence, the organizational mode also provides the
basis for fictional information, that is, for a core element of literature.
So far, the capability
to perform adaptations in the organizational mode would indeed be an
indispensable and constitutive property of all forms of art. However, it
extends beyond the traditional scope of the arts in that it is also a
precondition for numerous other cultural activities, from general learning by
exercise, through dance, conviviality, cooking, and religious service, up to
the Finnish ‘art’ of wife carrying and the Australian ‘art’ of dwarf tossing.
To put it academically: this capability is not a sufficient but necessary
condition of what we call ‘art.’ Moreover, the organizational mode, in the
context of human behavior, not only serves ontogenetically to adapt the
individual organism to a given environment but also to display, discuss, and
culturally shape this environment. As is generally known, most animals are
disposed to play only in their youth; as soon as they have acquired the
necessary routines, however, their behavior becomes severe and inflexible. The
fact that humans are ‘playing’ throughout their entire lifespan renders their
behavior far more flexible than that of their animal relatives—and, at the same
time, more insecure. Humans need culture, because culture builds the
‘in-between worlds’ (Eibl, “Zwischenwelten”) which regulate, by means of
standardization, the mutual adjustment between the changing world and the
evolved nervous system. Mere play, Pinker’s pure pleasure behavior, thus rather
turns out to be a limiting case. In the standard case, playful behaviors are,
in the sense of a ‘secondary severity’ (Eibl, “Zwei Kulturen,” 38ff.),
superimposed by new, and frequently culturally conditioned, functions such as,
for instance, cultivating informational secureness, reducing contingency, and
constantly practicing social consensus.
One might regard this
as an evidence for the particular ‘adaptiveness’ of the arts. However, one
would have to acknowledge that the function of providing imaginative in-between
worlds and producing “meaning” can just as well be achieved by other,
non-artistic, cultural phenomena such as law texts, traffic rules, science, or
morals. Hence, we do not think that the arts are “an adaptive response to the
adaptive problem produced by the adaptive capacities of high intelligence”
(target article); here we would prefer to put “culture”. ‘The arts’, we think,
have not one biologically adaptive function, but many cultural functions. This
leads to the third step of analysis: the question for the culturally specific
inter-relation of innate dispositions and actual conditions and requirements.
Pursuing this question
may reveal that an evolutionary heuristics not only opens up new aspects within
general literary theory but can also enter the realm of historicist analysis
and be of valuable assistance there. First, the evolutionary approach can
explain how, and on the basis of which innate adaptations, certain cultural
phenomena could come into being at all. There is, for instance, no conception
of the ‘sublime’ without innate fear stimuli (Mellmann, Emotionalisierung,
92ff., 231ff.); there is no delight in detective novels without a ‘cheater
detector.’ and so on.—Secondly, a comparison of the original adaptive functions
of a behavior and its actual cultural ones can help to define the culturally
specific more precisely. To give an example: naturalists have rightly argued
against the assumption that romantic love is ‘merely’ a social construct.
However, one should keep in mind that the hypothesis of romantic love as a
cultural ‘invention’ is based upon an important and accurate observation.
Passionate love, understood as an innate psychic module for adaptive mate
choice (Fisher), has presumably always existed. Why, however, on the ground of
this general human experience, the sophisticated (predominantly literary)
technique of self articulation and world depiction developed in the course of
the eighteenth century cannot be answered but in a cultural-historical
perspective. It is therefore not enough to refute radical statements from
social constructivists. Instead, we should specify them further and let them
gain new relevance by adding the evolutionary perspective.
Carroll also highlights
the cultural superimposition on human nature when he remarks (with Wilson): “We
do not have the option of living outside our own imaginative constructs.”
However, two additional considerations are necessary here. Biologists should
pay attention to the fact that not only products of the arts provide us with
imaginative constructs but that our entire culture essentially consists of
constructs; and culturalists should pay attention to the fact that those
constructs are by no means free inventions but are built on elements of our
biological inheritance and still have to stand the test of their evolutionary
environment.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Department of Religious Studies
University of Calgary
Carroll offers a wide-ranging survey of
"literary Darwinism." Along with his prior surveys, it will certainly
serve as a starting point for research in what he hopes will become a
burgeoning field. He is, however, rightly concerned that this new angle on the
critical analysis of literature should not become another erratic on the plains
of the post-modern glaciation. Recognizing the possiblity of a fresh start,
grounded on the foundations of the historical sciences, his ultimate hope is
for literary Darwinism to contribute new knowledge. If this is plausible, it
could add to the storehouse of consilient knowledge that has emerged from
Darwin's holistic evolutionary perspective. That, certainly, would be something
that literary criticism has not attempted or been known for, of recent. The
basis for optimism regarding the possibility of creating new knowledge in
literary Darwinism is sound—nothing less than the holistic ecology of evolutionary
biology and the interconnections of emergent complexity in the cosmos (Kauffman
119). The literary Darwinists reviewed by Carroll attempting to describe the
manifestation of this interconnectedness at the level of human culture and
reflection. Tenuous as first steps may be, we see here a solid foundation from
which to escape the political forms that have stymied humanistic scholarship.
Carroll's optimism regarding the
possibilities for a new contribution to knowledge draws our attention directly
to manifestations of evolutionary nature in literature and the arts and
particularly to the disputed topic of human universals. Universals are
central adaptive characteristics that have emerged as the human species
interacted with its terrestrial environment over millions of years. Of course
some foundational elements of these universals emerged before humans, making
their cultural expression the more powerful and universal (Shubin 27). The
basic responses and emotions deriving from the biological prime directives
(survival and reproduction) are pre-human and constitute the core of perennial
literary themes such as love and war. Identifying and describing the
manifestation of these universals in literature and the arts is the first great
challenge in implementing literary Darwinism as a practical criticism.
Repeatedly in Carroll's survey of existing research, one senses a struggle to
make the connection between the simple elegance of the Darwinian mythos and the
cultural and psychological complexities of literature and the arts. The
surveyed results offer a quilt-work of suggestions ranging from the fundamental
to the overwrought. So, for example, Brian Boyd's hypothesis that literature is
"cognitive play that develops creativity and helps form social identity"
(in target article) seems only weakly connected to the temporal character of
literature. Under the heading "The Adaptive Function of
Literature,"similar suppositions (focusing attention on adaptive salients
(Dissanayake), focusing shared attention (Boyd), and social cohesion (Boyd and
Dissanayake) do not seem to possess the low-level hooks that one looks for in a
biologically rooted cultural form. Carroll himself observes that the suggested
adaptive functionality of enhancing creativity is not specific to the arts;
technology does this as well.
In several places Carroll describes
observations that converge on a connection between a basic literary form and a
primary environmental condition. In an earlier book, Evolution and Literary
Theory, Carroll linked several literary phenomena under the rubric
"cognitive mapping" (in target article). Several independent studies
in his survey agree that the link between story and environmental processes
lies near the centre of literature's adaptive function (for example, Panksepp
& Panksepp; E.O. Wilson's scenario machine; Tooby & Cosmides'
"powerful organizing effect"). Carroll extrapolates this function
from narrative to the arts generally. Although this linkage may be apparent in
other arts of spatio-temporal representation, generalization at this point
seems a mistake. The focus on story and its direct connection to environmental
events is a solid lead, the best and broadest example of human ecology evoking
literature. E.O. Wilson's surmise that literature and the other arts meet some
deep emotional needs ([the] "need to produce and consume imaginative
artifacts would be as real and distinct a need as hunger, sex, or social
interaction") is derivative from this fundamental functionality. Given the
early stage of literary Darwinism it seems advisable for primary energies to
concentrate on the basics. A focus on the narrative form of literature provides
two important linkages for literary Darwinism: one, an immediate linkage with
the orienting Darwinian narrative of life; the other, a connection between a
cultural form and the pervasive environmental condition of causally connected
events. Like many of the stories from the ancient world that achieved
"classic" status, the Darwinian story of evolution provides an encompassing
narrative, mirroring and mapping the natural historical processes in which
humans find themselves. Although a great deal of human adaptation is
unconscious and genetically based, literature is at least partly a product of
conscious adaptation. And at the centre of literary structures of
representation we find story -- a representation of the matrix of environmental
events and agentive behaviours that constitute the human environment. Stories
are "cognitive maps" (in the target article) by which conscious adapters
navigate, remember, and communicate valuable information about their
environment. Of course cognitive maps were not, in the first instance, full
blown literature. The novel comes much later, but the simple beginnings of
story certainly would have provided human ancestors with a competitive edge
over other organisms relying on comparatively glacial and unreflective genetic
memories. The same holds true with regard to inter-human competition. Groups
with the most accurate stories would also have been in a position of
competitive advantage (just as Darwin saw that those with the greatest internal
cohesion would be ahead of the others.[35]
Carroll's concern
that the new Darwinian perspective should not become just another critical
approach is justified. Academic libraries are stuffed with scholarship that
takes more space on shelves than in heads. Darwinism teaches us to ask what
something is for, what its adaptive purpose is. When something loses utility it
atrophies and turns to dust, an alarm raised by the dusty volumes in academic
libraries. So what hope is there for a Darwinian approach to make a
contribution in its native environment, where fame may be built on the
biophobic perception that culture has escaped its natural ecology (cited in the
target article)? Perhaps the best course would be for literary Darwinism to
take a chance and stop trying to reform the old haunts of literature and the
arts. Carroll mentions conference proposal rejections for a Darwinian
perspective perceived as not on the post-modern edge. I expect that his
experiences have been duplicated many times. What, then, about a contribution
not to literature and the arts but rather along the lines of one of the oldest
forms of humanistic reflection? "Know thyself": for the last 150 years
or so, many of the most penetrating insights into the human condition have come
from Darwinism and the historical sciences. "Darwinian literary
studies" marries an evolutionary framework that provides a new critical
perspective with the natural reflective qualities of the best in literature.
Taken together and set on new page uncoloured by the politics of humanistic
discourse there is a good hope that literary Darwinism might add at least some
of the self- knowledge we seem to need to steer culture's course back toward
something fit for nature's ecology.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Jeffrey E. Foy
Stony Brook University
Richard J. Gerrig
Stony Brook University
Please address correspondence to:
Jeffrey E. Foy
Department of Psychology
Stony Brook University
Stony Brook, NY 11794-2500
phone: (631) 632-7847
fax: (631) 632-7876
email: jefoy@notes.cc.sunysb.edu
Literature
enriches human experience, as Carroll and other evolutionary theorists have
pointed out. Many positive aspects of literature, such as how it can be used to
transmit social information and how it can help people organize knowledge about
the world, have been highlighted recently by evolutionary theorists (Boyd,
“Evolutionary”; Scalise Sugiyama, “Reverse-Engineering”). As Carroll’s essay
indicates, there is an on-going debate about whether the capacity to produce
and comprehend narratives is an adaptation or is parasitic on other evolved
cognitive abilities. We suggest that this debate should be more informed by the
possible negative—and sometimes maladaptive—consequences of the human species’
capacity to experience narrative and engage in imagination.
Researchers have argued that fiction
allows people to simulate new experiences and vicariously learn about new
situations (Mar Oatley; Scalise Sugiyama, “Reverse-Engineering”). These
analyses have suggested that people expand their social knowledge through
narratives, allowing them to learn about how society deals with things from
marriage to murder. Through narratives, people learn what is expected of them
and how to behave in new situations in accordance with societal norms.
Narratives also bolster the ability to understand what is happening in the
minds of other people. Many narratives allow people to take a different
perspective, such as the perspective of somebody of the opposite gender. When
people engage in social interactions, they may draw on the knowledge gained
from narratives to help interact more smoothly. In that way, narratives play an
important role in passing on social knowledge.
While this analysis suggests that
narrative plays an explicitly prosocial role in human development, we would do
well to recall why Plato expressed a strong fear that stories could have a
negative impact on children’s moral development. In the Republic, Plato notes that “poets
and story-tellers are in error in matters of the greatest human importance.
They have said that unjust men are often happy and just men wretched, that
wrong-doing pays if you can avoid being found out, and that justice is good for
someone else but is to your own disadvantage” (Lee translation 148-149). For
these reasons, we must be concerned that literature has the potential to
corrupt.
In fact, researchers have
demonstrated that, after reading a moderately engaging story, people will express
more agreement with statements that straightforwardly contradict real-world
truths (e.g., that mental illnesses are contagious) (Prentice, Gerrig, and
Bailis; see also Wheeler, Green, and Brock). Narrative impact does not fade
quickly: When compared to immediate tests, readers’ beliefs were more
influenced by the story content two weeks after reading a story (Appel and
Richter). When readers experience a strong sense of being transported to a
narrative world—when they give reports of focused mental involvement with the
story—they are also more likely to modify their beliefs and attitudes in the
direction of the story (Green and Brock, “The Role”). The experience of being
transported effectively reduces readers’ motivation to argue against information
presented in a story (Green and Brock, “Mind’s Eye”; and Prentice and Gerrig). Those
works of literature that most effectively immerse their readers have the
greatest potential to do both good and harm. The question becomes what
distribution of information is actually made available through texts. Plato’s
characterization of the lessons offered by poets and story-tellers has great
contemporary resonance. How can we be certain that, on balance, it’s a good
thing that readers absorb lessons from literature?
As an example of why we might be concerned,
consider the question of whether exposure to televised aggression has a
negative impact on people’s subsequent behavior. To address this question,
Huesmann, Moise-Titus, Podolski, and Eron undertook a longitudinal study.
Beginning in 1977, the researchers spent two years recording the extent to
which 557 first- and third-grade children watched TV shows with violent
content. Fifteen years later, the researchers were able to locate 329 of those
children (as 20- to 22-year-olds). The participants’ adult levels of aggression
were assessed both through self-reports and other-reports (from individuals
such as spouses). The data revealed a clear pattern: For both men and women,
those individuals who had viewed the most televised violence in grade school
displayed the highest levels of aggression as adults. The researchers used
other data to argue against the possibility that the predilection toward
aggression comes first (e.g., the data showed only a small relationship between
childhood aggression and the individuals’ viewing of TV violence as adults).
Thus, the data suggest that the lessons children absorbed from violent
narratives predicted later aggression.
Of course, the human species’
capacity to experience narrative evolved well before the advent of television.
For that reason, we are on dodgy ground when we invoke contemporary examples to
reflect on literature as a means for instruction. That point is equally true
whether those examples serve to illustrate the potential for good or the
potential for harm. Still, any discussion of the processes by which readers
acquire information from literature should not ignore the potential for harm.
Another argument in favor of the
adaptive value of literature has centered on the virtues of imagination. Imagination,
which plays a key role in our understanding of narratives, plays an important
role in our everyday life. As Carroll states in the target article, “We live in
the imagination. No action or event is, for humans, ever just itself. It is
always a component in mental representations of the natural and social order,
extending over time.” However, other commentators have noted that the “longing
to lose ourselves in fiction” incurs “the dangers of confusing fantasy with reality”
(Pinker, “Towards a Consilient Study” 163). Research in psychology suggests
that those dangers are quite genuine.
Studies on false
memories have demonstrated that people confuse events that they have only
imagined with events that really occurred. Consider a study by Thomas and
Loftus that unfolded over two weeks. In an initial experimental session, the
researchers asked the participants either to perform certain actions (such as
bouncing a ball on the floor) or to imagine doing the actions. Twenty-four
hours later, participants returned to the laboratory and only imagined
themselves performing actions—including some from the previous day—from one to
five times. Two weeks later, the participants returned and attempted to
discriminate between those actions they had actually performed and those that
they had only imagined. Many of the participants claimed to have performed some
of the actions that they only imagined, including bizarre events such as
balancing spoons on their nose or sitting on dice. The more times an action was
imagined, the more likely it was that people would falsely claim to have
performed the action. Experiments of this sort demonstrate the permeability of
the boundary between the imagination and reality.
In fact, the
permeability of this boundary gives rise to behavior that is explicitly
maladaptive. Consider the experiences of individuals who suffer from
obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD). OCD is characterized by
obsessions—persistent, recurring inappropriate thoughts—that intrude on a
person’s consciousness in a way that causes anxiety and compulsions—repetitive,
purposeful behaviors—that function to neutralize anxiety (DSM-IV). For
example, “individuals with obsessions about being contaminated may reduce their
mental distress by washing their hands until their skin is raw” (DSM-IV 418).
At some point in their lives, 1.6% of U.S. adults experience the disorder
(Kessler, Berglund, Demler, Jin, Mrikangas, and Walters). Researchers have
suggested that, in the experience of OCD, “imagination plays a decisive role in
rendering remote possibilities more probable” (Aardema and O’Connor 194).
Consider this case report from a patient: “I could be crazy enough to cut out
my tongue. When I’m anxious, I can ‘see’ myself doing it, using a knife to cut
it off. It feels like I could actually do it” (O’Connor, Aardema and Pélissier
121 as cited in Aardema and O’Connor). Such obsessions represent circumstances
in which “the imagination is informed not by objective criteria but by a
persuasive narrative leading the person to treat a possibility as reality”
(Aardema and O’Connor 190). Thus, as possibilities migrate from the
imagination, OCD sufferers begin to engage in behaviors that have a negative
impact on their day-to-day functioning. This is one consequence of the human
imagination. OCD is just one example of circumstances in which “believed-in
imaginings” have potential negative consequences (see de Rivera and Sarbin).
As we noted at the
outset, Carroll and others have called attention to the various ways in which
literature enriches human experience. We are inclined to agree with that
assessment. However, we have attempted to illustrate why the potential for good
and the potential for harm should be evaluated side-by-side. By recognizing
circumstances in which experiences of narrative and uses of imagination may
have negative consequences, theorists can enter into a more nuanced debate
about particular evolutionary analyses.
Authors’ Note
This material is based upon work supported by National Science
Foundation Grant No. 0325188. Any opinions, findings, and conclusions or
recommendations expressed in this material are those of the author and do not
necessarily reflect the views of the National Science Foundation. We thank
Matthew Jacovina and Benjamin Swets for helpful comments.
*************************************************************************************************************************
Harold Fromm
University of Arizona
Joseph Carroll’s overview of an
evolutionary paradigm for literary study is so comprehensive and lucid that
there isn’t very much I would care to criticize. But I would like to
expand its reaches. The whole notion of “human nature” has had a fairly bad
history, exploited as it has been to reinforce conservative and reactionary
programs to force human beings into conformity with transient social
imperatives. Homer and Nature may have been the same for Alexander Pope, and
Jon Gottschall does very well with his literary analyses of The Iliad in
terms of the updated human nature that has been so improved upon by biology and
neuroscience, but we obviously will continue to need revised contemporary
models. Freud’s picture of human nature now strikes us as verging on the
bizarre: penis-envy, myths buried in neurons somehow inscripted with Oedipus
and Elektra? Put otherwise, “human nature” as a concept needs to be open-ended,
since its particular biological foundations will be subject to revision like
all scientific truths. Even Joseph Carroll, coming as he does from Victorian
Studies and its constitutive elements, such as the 19th century
novel, is bound to seem limited by criteria that eventually won’t appear as
“scientific” as he would hope, since “scientific” is best understood along a
sliding scale. (Think of the pre-Foucauldian misdirections of Thomas Kuhn.)
Scientists themselves tend not to speak of
“the” scientific method. Alan Sokal, a physicist notorious for his famous hoax,
speaks in his new book of “epistemological opportunism” as the best bet for
validation in the sciences, since there is no single “method” that equals
“science” (249 et passim). And one need only consider all the clinical
trials for food nutrients, anti-cancer drugs, regimens for warding off
Alzheimer’s, macular degeneration, and colon cancer (flat lesions being the
latest discovery) to see how radically revisionary the most widely researched conclusions
tend to be. In the more discursive sciences, such as evolutionary psychology,
interpretation is perhaps the chief and most vulnerable technique. Even
statistical findings fail to speak for themselves as we have already seen in
the above examples from the hard sciences. And speaking personally, when it
comes to the humanities, I react to the use of “scientific” as if it were
metaphor. I probably would feel more at ease with “in the spirit of the
sciences.” I say these things as a believer in the various post-Darwinian
sciences who nevertheless suffers from a fear of triumphalism.
So there are still
lots of worlds to conquer that will have been totally neglected or denied by
all sorts of conventions and proprieties as well as research questions not
asked because not even thought of. Jon Gottschall and his students did not find
unsurfaced, unacknowledged, unwitting conventions or needs in folk and fairy
tales from around the world and Joe Carroll does not find them in Victorian
literature. Taboos are unspoken even as they are operative while “invisible.”
But what you don’t ask you’re unlikely to find. And of course, you can’t ask
about things you know nothing about. There’s a growth industry out there.
“Reality” is in little danger of being used up. Ph. D. students, nota bene!
*************************************************************************************************************************
Do We Need Literary Darwinism?
Eugene Goodheart
In his essay, “The Sleep of Reason” the
philosopher Thomas Nagel remarks: “[Postmodernism] may be on the way out, but I
suspect that there will continue to be a market in the huge American academy
for a quick fix of some kind. If it is not social constructionism, it will be
something else—Darwinian explanations of practically everything else” (Patai
and Corral 552). Now associated with extraordinary advances in genetics,
Darwinism promises a scientific understanding of any and all disciplines in the
humanities and the social sciences. Think of postmodern skepticism about words
like “truth” and “reality.” The neo-Darwinian approach removes the quotation
marks that surround them. As I say in my book, Darwinian Misadventures in
the Humanities, “I would be less than candid not to acknowledge that the
present condition in the humanities (its self-doubt and disarray) is a kind of
invitation to the neo-Darwinists” (1). E. O. Wilson, founder of sociobiology,
draws the following contrast between the Enlightenment tradition in which he
places himself and postmodernism. “Postmodernism is the ultimate polar
antithesis to the Enlightenment. The difference between the two extremes could
be explained as follows. Enlightenment thinkers believe we can know everything,
and radical postmodernists believe we can know nothing” (Consilience
44). This is a debatable formulation, but it does reveal the mindset of the
neo-Darwinian approach. In his book Consilience Wilson has no less an
ambition than to unify all the disciplines on the basis of biology. The
ultimate ambition of literary Darwinism, as Joseph Carroll makes clear very
much in the Wilsonian spirit, is “to fundamentally [alter] the paradigm within which
literary study is now conducted” and “to subsume all other possible approaches
to literary study.” Historical, aesthetic, sociological, rhetorical
perspectives are to be incorporated into a predominantly biological approach to
literature. Though Carroll acknowledges that theoretical approaches other than
literary Darwinism have provided insights into literature, he sees them as all
flawed, requiring their rescue by evolutionary psychology. The chutzpah is
breathtaking, given the absence of anything approaching a theory of literature
in the paradigm he presents.
Can evolutionary
psychology say anything interesting about literature? my answer is that it is
possible, that I am not a prophet and can’t predict the future. On the basis of
what I’ve read up to now, I must confess that I am a skeptic. Both the general
understanding of literature and the interpretations of individual works are
crudely reductionist. Reductionism in the natural sciences is no vice; on the
contrary, it enables one discipline (for instance, physics) to explain another
(chemistry). In the humanities, however, it subverts the uniqueness and
complexity of works of art. Carroll’s complaint about “traditional humanist
criticism,” (which I exemplify in his essay) is that lacking in empirical
curiosity, it “operates on the level of the author’s lexicon and seeks no
systematic reduction to simple principles that have large general validity” (Literary
Darwinism 213). Well, this hardly seems a deficiency. The alternative that
Carroll and his fellow literary Darwinists propose is the dissolution of the
individuality of a work (the very reason that we enjoy and value it) into large
generalizations that removes all of its distinctive features and vitality.
Here are some samples, striking in their banality:
“Humans are bipedal, but proportional to body size they have much larger brains
than other primates.... Human beings are heavily dependent on parental care for
much longer than other animals…Parents and children share a fitness interest in
the success of the child—in the child reaching maturity and achieving
successful reproduction…Human beings are physically discrete. Individual
persons are bodies wrapped in skin with nervous systems to brains that are
soaked in blood and encased in bone.” And then there is the occasional sentence
of stupefying opacity: “The arts are thus an adaptive response to the adaptive
problem produced by the adaptive capacities of high intelligence.” I would
think that a detailed attention to particular works of literature would be a
mark of empiricism. None is forthcoming in Carroll’s essay. Despite its claim
to be empirical, literary Darwinism encourages readers to find confirmation of
what evolutionary psychology determines to be psychological truth rather than
being open to what a work of literature does or says.
Worse, straining to find to find such
confirmation the result may be an exercise in irrelevance as when David and
Nanelle Barash offer up the following in their grotesquely titled book Madame
Bovary’s Ovaries.
Like the rest of us [Othello] has been restricted to just one Desdemona
at a time. [Where in the play is there the suggestion that Othello feels
restricted in his love for Desdemona?]…During the rut, bull elk are notoriously
aggressive and intolerant of each other, while cow elk are comparatively
placid; even among monogamous songbirds, males regularly patrol their
territories, alert for intruders. [What do the rutting habits of bull elk have
to do with Othello’s behavior in the play?] …It is also worth noting that
Othello is considerably older than Desdemona, a pattern that lends itself to an
additional slate of evolutionary insights. Yet another biological asymmetry
between sexes is that whereas women go through menopause, men remain
potentially reproductive into old age” [Neither Desdemona’s menopause nor
Othello’s putative geriatric fertility figures in the play.] (20,21).
If it weren’t for the obvious seriousness of the authors, we might
think that we were being treated to a parody of literary interpretation. The
book, listed in Carroll’s bibliography, has the endorsement of none other that
E. O. Wilson, who speaks of it as an “account of an important new development
in literary criticism: the incorporation of the biology of human nature.”
The key idea in Carroll’s account of the
evolutionary paradigm for literary study is that “humans have evolved in an
adaptive relation to their environment.” This is accomplished through the
agency of natural selection, “shaping motives and emotions so as to maximize
the chances that an organism will propagate its genes, or copies of its genes
in its kin.” It would then follow that the writing and the reading of works of
literature help in the adaptation, a plausible but hardly comprehensive claim
for the whole of literature. I can think of many major works of literature that
have the contrary effect of unsettling our relation to the environment. How
does King Lear or Gulliver Travels or Kafka’s The
Metamorphosis illustrate the adaptive function of literature? A person in
the bourgeois comfort of her home would do well to avoid reading any of these
works if she wished to maximize her chances for a successful adaptation to the
environment. Not a word in Carroll’s benign paradigm of evolutionary psychology
on the nihilistic, genocidal propensities of tribes and nations. His depiction
of human nature has a comfortable middle class setting.
Carroll takes me to task for not being
truly interested in what constitutes human nature. Of course, I want to know as
much as possible about human nature. As I made clear in my book, I do not share
the postmodern view that human nature is a blank slate. I am, however,
skeptical about the confidence of evolutionary psychologists that their
putative knowledge of human nature gives them the authority to interpret and
evaluate literature. In quoting my sentence, “human nature may not be a blank
slate, but do we know enough to know what is inscribed upon it,” Carroll fails
to provide the context for it, Steven Pinker’s blinkered wholesale repudiation
of modern and postmodern in The Blank Slate. Unhappy about the condition
of modern art, he wants to answer the question of why “the arts are in
trouble.” And he finds the answer in Virginia Woolf’s misguided statement that
human nature changed in 1910. So, in Pinker’s view, modernism, mistakenly
proceeding as if human nature has changed, abandoned realism in literature in
which works unfold from beginnings through middles to endings in true
Aristotelian fashion for narratives of indeterminate structures, and it
rejected representational art for paintings that are “freakish distortions of
shape and color and,,, abstract grids, shapes, dribbles, splashes” (15) and so
on. The modernist literature of Joyce and Proust, the modernist art of Picasso
and Braque and the postmodernist art of Jackson Pollack among many others are
judged to be violations of human nature, according to a scientific,
evolutionary psychological understanding of it. Human nature for Pinker turns
out to be the exercise of bourgeois virtues. “The fact is that the values of
the middle class—personal responsibility, devotion to family, and neighborhood,
avoidance of macho violence, respect for liberal democracy are good things, not
bad things. Most of the world wants to join the bourgeoisie, and most artists
are members in good standing who adopted a few bohemian affectations” (18) Pinker
defends bourgeois virtues, which are real, but he writes about them as if they
are pieties immune to criticism, so much for Stendhal, Flaubert and Baudelaire
and so much for a disinterested scientific treatment of the subject.
Is it unreasonable to wonder about an
evolutionary psychologist’s claim to knowledge about human nature when it is
the basis for a wholesale rejection of a body of great literature? The effect
of Pinker’s approach is prescription and proscription. It is not literature and
the arts that explore the unchartered territory of human nature, but “science”
that is supposed to establish what human nature is and in effect police
literature and the arts. Rather than being open to the creative surprises of
the literary imagination, the evolutionary psychologist seeks confirmation for
his theory in literature and when he doesn’t find it, it is literature that is
at fault. It is hard to see either science or critical illumination of
literature and the arts in such an approach. Taken seriously, Pinker’s
philistine view would inhibit rather than foster the creative imagination. I
would be curious to know Carroll’s opinion about Pinker’s approach.
Natural selection is a driving, if not the driving, force
in evolutionary theory. Human life is a result of natural selection, but
intelligent design has a large role to play in human achievements. It is not at
all clear how the mindless activity of genes contributes to the making and the
understanding of literature and the arts. Aware of the problem, Richard
Dawkins, perhaps the most fervent advocate of the neo-Darwinian synthesis, has
proposed an amendment to “the genetic history of mankind.” He has introduced
“the meme” as a cultural counterpart to the gene. “Mimeme comes from a suitable
Greek root, but I want a monosyllable that sounds a bit like ‘gene’… it could
alternately be thought of as relating to ‘memory’ or to the French word meme”
(The Selfish Gene 18). Examples of the meme are physical embodiments of
ideas such as “the wheel,” “calculus,” “chess,” “impressionism.” Memes like
genes replicate themselves. What is not evident is how they produce cultural
variation. Take the instance of impressionism: how does the meme produce the
differences among Renoir, Pissarro and Monet? The concept is the product of
speculation—without any empirical or experimental basis as far as I know. Enough
to say that the conception of the role of culture in the neo-Darwinian synthesis
is rudimentary and hardly justifies the high confidence of its advocates in
their forays in the studies of literature and the arts. Aristotle’s Poetics
is grounded in his conception of biology, but he knew, as the current breed of
Darwinists don’t seem to know, that you need to have both a theory of
literature and a literary sensibility that produce results when you engage a
particular work of literature and not be content simply with generalities about
human nature. Are their biological components in the making and understanding
of literature and the arts? I am sure there are. My main objection is to the
attempt to turn evolutionary psychology into a systematic approach to
literature, comparable to a Freudian or Marxist or Structuralist approach. The
result would be disastrously Procrustean.
What Are Literary Scholars For? What is Art For?
Washington and Jefferson College
On May 11 2008 I published an article in
the Ideas section of the Sunday Boston Globe called "Measure for
Measure." The article was basically a précis of my book Literature,
Science, and a New Humanities, and it sounded many of the same themes that
dominate Professor Carroll's target article.
Like Carroll, I argued
for a fairly radical solution to the malaise in academic literary study: we
should study the successes of the sciences and, insofar as possible, we should try
to emulate them. Also like Carroll, I did not argue that scientific tools can
replace judgment, imagination, erudition, or good scholarship. I argued that
combining these humanistic virtues with scientific tools would create new
synergies (I find Carroll's synergistic vision for the future of the
discipline, expressed in his conclusion, entirely appealing and entirely
achievable). In the digital age, a counter-intuitive argument appearing in a
high-profile forum instantly becomes a target article itself. By now about one
hundred bloggers have weighed in on my article.
The blog is a genre for impulsive rants,
and in addition to substantive critique, posts about my article are rife with
ridicule and ad hominem. To many bloggers the Globe article
marked me as "pathetic," a "philistine," a "bullshit
artist," a peddler of ignorant "tosh" and "silly
scientism," and "a tenured nitwit" (alas, not even tenure-track,
in reality). There were positive responses too. One blogger said that the
article gave him a "man crush" and inspired "explosively
incontinent affection" (er, thanks). But the positive responses were
dominated by people who are deeply disaffected by what one blogger called the
"useless nonsense" and "inane babbling" of contemporary
literary study. I had the feeling that many of these writers would applaud
anything smiting standard practices in the field.
I predict that Carroll's target article
will receive robust support from respondents who are already committed to a
consilient, biocultural approach, but there will also be many stridently negative
responses which--while robed in academic niceties--will seethe with the kind of
resentment that was freely vented in the blogoshperic reaction to my Globe
article.
I think all of the sound and fury about a
more scientific approach to literary study signifies a deep rift in
intellectual culture about the raison d'etre of literary scholarship.
Carroll references this rift in his overview of disciplinary history,
Literary criticism over the past century has spread itself along a
continuum between two poles. At the one pole, eclectic general knowledge
provides a framework for impressionistic and improvisatory commentary. At the
other pole, some established school of thought, in some domain not specifically
literary, provides a more systematic vocabulary for the description and
analysis of literary texts.
Obviously, naturalistic literary study has most in common with the
latter pole, and that may make it seem like merely the latest attempt to force
a grand, faddish "theory of everything" onto the field--like Marxism
or psychoanalysis or poststructuralism. But this actually underrates the
radicalism and ambition of Carroll's vision. Carroll is not only arguing for
reinterpreting texts through the lens of consilient knowledge, he is arguing
for a wholesale disciplinary migration toward a scientific ethos.
In so doing, Carroll is making an argument
about the ultimate point of literary scholarship. This comes through in the
final section of the essay where he argues that the most serious challenge for the Darwinists is this:
can we "produce formulations that are not only new but true?" Can we
produce "new knowledge—real knowledge, knowledge that is consilient with
the broader world of empirical research"?
So for Carroll, and
for me, the ultimate test of a literary paradigm is whether or not it succeeds
in making durable contributions to the sum of human understanding. And his
critique of the currently dominating paradigm—expressed here rather gently, and
in his earlier writings rather less so--is that it has spectacularly failed to
do so.
I think Carroll is
right about this. But there are at least two ways in which we both might be
wrong.
First, it may be that we have simply missed
the point. It may be that the raison d'être of professional literary
study is not knowledge accumulation. This position was recently
expressed to me by a good friend over beers. In the course of our conversation,
I was able to corner him and make him admit that Freud was in all probability
wrong about The Oedipus Complex and that Lacan was in all probability wrong
about The Mirror Stage. But I could not convince him that psychoanalysis's weak
claim to explanatory validity meant that it should be drummed out of literary
theory. My friend says he will still teach the tenets of psychoanalytic
criticism in literary theory class, not because he thinks they have truth value
but because they "are still illuminating, they bring out pattern." So,
for my friend, the ultimate point of literary study is not to accumulate
knowledge that is "truer" than what we possessed before. For him, the
point of professional literary study is harder to express, but it involves
appreciation, imaginative play, self-improvement, and cognitive exercise. (Note
that the issue is not how people ought to read literature. It is about
what professional literary scholars are supposed to be producing when doing
their jobs.)
On the other hand, many respondents might
agree with Carroll that the ultimate purpose of literary scholarship is to
accumulate more reliable knowledge about the subject, but vehemently disagree
about how we should go about this. Carroll proceeds on the assumption that
there is no real barrier between the sciences and humanities, no wall or moat
or prophylactic of any kind that blocks the application of scientific tools to
humanities questions. Humanities questions are often deeply complex (as are
questions in the life and social sciences), but they are not irreducibly
complex. I share Carroll's conviction. But if reaction from the blogosphere is
any barometer, this is a minority view. Most would feel that any proposal for
"literary science" would be risibly (if not pathetically) oxymoronic;
such a proposal would signal a stunning failure to grasp that literary scholars
and scientists are studying fundamentally, radically different
kinds of stuff.
There are
signs that scholars are girding up for a big fight about the role of scientific
theory, method, and ethos in humanities scholarship. Happily, however, the
question of whether or not scientific tools can help humanists generate more
reliable knowledge is not one of those academic disputes that has to drag on and
on until everyone gets exhausted and gives up. This is a dispute that will
yield to empirical evidence. Either movement toward a more scientific paradigm
in literary studies will yield superior results (of the kind Carroll describes
in the conclusion to his article) or it won't. As E. O. Wilson wrote in his preface
to The Literary Animal, "There is only one way to settle the issue
[of whether the humanities are consilient with the sciences]: Go there and find
out; utilize Francis Bacon's dictum that truth comes more easily out of error
than out of confusion" (vii).
***
Shifting lanes, I will respond
briefly to Carroll's discussion of controversies about the possible adaptive
function(s) of fictional narrative and other art forms. Natural selection is a
ruthlessly utilitarian process. So the question is, Why art? Why should humans
spend (waste?) so much time with this stuff? Why did our ancestors choose to
consume or compose songs or tales or poetry when they could have been out
courting mates or stalking food—finding direct ways of passing on their genes? Shouldn't
individuals and groups that engaged in seemingly wasteful activities like
making visual art or telling tales have been rapidly out-competed and displaced
by those who kept their eyes on the ultimate evolutionary prize: sustaining
survival in order to produce more and healthier offspring?
Steven Pinker has argued that art
forms may have no genetic benefits at all—they may simply be, as Carroll puts
it, "parasitic side effects of cognitive aptitudes that evolved for other
functions." (Pinker makes a possible exception for fictional narrative,
which he believes may have conferred adaptive benefits as a sort of virtual
reality simulator). As Carroll acknowledges, humanists who have grappled with this
evolutionary riddle have typically preferred adaptive explanations and have
been highly critical of by-product explanations like Pinker's. As Carroll notes,
a frequent argument against by-product has been to "observe that since the
arts consume vast amounts of human time and effort, selection would have worked
against retaining them if they had no adaptive value."
This argument has been
made by several theorists, but it is framed with most vigor and precision by
Brian Boyd in his forthcoming book, On the Origin of Stories: Evolution,
Cognition, Fiction:
If the byproduct hypothesis
were correct, then over thousands of generations and millions of births,
individuals and societies with a lesser disposition to art would have
prospered, because they did not incur the high costs of art and either simply
had more opportunity to rest and harbor resources—like other top predators,
such as big cats—or had more to time and energy to devote to activities that
did yield benefits, such as producing new resources or competing to acquire the
resources of others. These more ruthlessly utilitarian and competitive realists
would have survived and reproduced in greater numbers, and over evolutionary
time their descendants would have supplanted those with a disposition to art.
Societies without any inclination to create their own dress, song and story
would have ousted those that did have these things. Individuals and groups
without art—without shared songs and dance (including anthems and war-dances),
without their own styles of dress and design (including face-paint,
scarification or tattoos, uniforms, emblems, flags, or monumental
architecture), without shared stories and sayings (including myths, heroic
legends, proverbs)—would fare better than those with all these things that art
makes possible. But that seems never to have been the case. No human society
lacks art, and the most successful societies have more art than ever before.[36]
My point is not that Boyd is wrong in his critique of the by-product
theory—clearly he has a point here, and there is more to his critique than this
snippet. Moreover, On the Origin of Stories marshals a stunning amount
of information from a broad swath of fields to offer compelling arguments for how
and why art propensities may have evolved. But I think Boyd and other theorists
have been too quick to reject by-product scenarios based, in part, on the logic
above.
The problem with this logic is that it
seems to all but rule out the possibility of a costly evolutionary by-product. Try
it out. Pick some other human trait and plug it into the argument above—just
make sure the trait carries costs. Instead of "art," substitute
"senescence." The argument would then read something like this,
"Senescence is an adaptation. Otherwise through the passages of deep time
individuals who did not senesce would outcompete those who did, and the high
fitness costs of getting old would have been selected against. Therefore since
senescence has high fitness costs, yet it still persists in all human
populations, it must confer adaptive advantages. In other words, getting old
and dying is better for ones genes than staying young and strong forever."
I'm choosing a semi-facetious example,
absolutely the first illustration that came to mind. But by the logic given
above, anything that currently exists, so long as it carries high costs,
must be adaptive. (So this logic would not apply to traits like the
redness of blood or the whiteness of bone—these can qualify as by-products
because they are cost-free.).
Now consider a more serious illustration. Think
of sickle cell anemia. No one thinks sickle cell is an adaptation. It is
literally the textbook illustration of a maladaptive byproduct of an adaptive
solution. Sickle cell is a damaging by-product of genes that have been favored,
in certain populations, because they confer malarial resistance. Genes for
sickle cell manage to persist because they are inextricably tied to genes for
malarial resistance. They persist because the huge benefits of malarial
resistance outweighed the smaller costs of a somewhat higher likelihood of
contracting sickle cell.
It could be the same with art. For now,
let's consider only narrative art. Boyd's
literature review amply demonstrates that humans are incorrigible gossips. We
have innate and insatiable hunger for strategic social information
because humans reap adaptive benefits when they understand the full complexity
of their social groups. Who is allied with whom? Who is sleeping with whom? Who
is plotting against whom? Who is dominant? Who is up and coming?
So here's a by-product scenario based on information
gleaned from Boyd's book. Enterprising individuals discover that they can rivet
attention (and hog up the good things that come with it—including enhanced
social status) by fabricating stories that are drippy with rich social information
about fictive persons (think Madame Bovary, The Tale of the Genji,
The Ramayana, The Arabian Nights, or almost anything else in
world literature, high or low, past or present). This could confer benefits on the tale teller while
inflicting costs on members of the audience. Even if there are real
costs to biological fitness associated with sitting around and listening to (or
reading) stories, that propensity might not be selected against if it were inextricably
knotted up with the bigger benefits of craving strategic social information--if,
in other words, selection couldn't act against our susceptibility to stories
without also acting against our adaptive craving for social information. In
this view, storytellers would be evolutionary parasites exploiting the
cognitive dispositions of their audiences. The strange human fascination with
stories about made-up people would be a by-product, not an adaptation.
I'm
not saying that I actually favor this specific by-product scenario or any
by-product scenario; in fact, based in large part on Boyd's total argument, I
think it is at least as likely that that humans possess art-specific
adaptations. I'm only saying that by-product scenarios strike me as plausible,
and that humanist theorists have been too quick to dismiss them.
There are now a broad variety of competing hypotheses (hostile commentators
would call them "just-so stories") for the riddle of art. All of
these hypotheses make predictions about what should be true about art, or
people's reactions to art, if the theory is true. Going forward, the big
challenge—and this applies as much to the scientists as the humanists--is to
start moving past the stage of generating and debating hypotheses and to begin
devising ingenious ways to test them scientifically. As with emerging
controversies over the merits of a more scientific approach to literary study,
there is a clear (though not easy) path toward resolving controversies about
the adaptive function of the arts: "Go there and find out; utilize Francis
Bacon's dictum that truth comes more easily out of error than out of confusion."
Professor in Film Studies at the Department of Media, Cognition, and Communication
University of Copenhagen.
Joseph Carroll’s target article “An
Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Studies” makes a bold argument for the
importance of an evolutionary perspective in the humanities, and it provides a
sweeping overview of the literary research based on evolutionary theory. Carroll
makes important arguments for the necessity of fusing methods and research
results from the humanities and the natural sciences and the necessity of
combining cognitive and evolutionary perspectives. (I make similar arguments in
Embodied Visions.) To build bridges between the sciences and the
humanities is a vital project if the humanities are to survive as a scholarly
endeavor.
Central to Carroll’s argument is to reopen
the question of Human Nature. Given the way social constructivism in sociology
and the humanities has neglected universals based on innate features of human
nature, this is a crucially important move. The question of human universals has
not been central to the study of fiction since the Structuralist era, and
social constructionists have falsely presupposed that the human brain has no
innate architecture and is thus infinitely malleable. Carroll argues
convincingly that the central themes in literature reflect problems that have
been vital to human survival. Further, Carroll’s emphasis on universalism
avoids an excessive reliance on a fine-grained modularity, and the critique of
massive modularity is a convincing argument for the role of culture in
establishing universal themes and structures. Carroll also gives an important
emphasis to the idea that culture can only be instantiated in individual brains
with specific life stories. In short, the target article is a great argument
for the value of evolutionary bioculturalism.
The most problematic part of the article is
the section on the adaptive function of literature, which raises many thorny
questions and problems. The central problem in the article is linked to the use
of the word “art.” Carroll wants both to define “what is peculiar and
essential” to art and to identify a specific adaptive problem that this
peculiar and essential mental disposition would have fulfilled in ancestral
environments. He further wants to identify design features that mediated this
adaptive function. The problems derive from the requirement that art should be
something peculiar and essential, since such an essentialist definition relies
on a rather historically specific understanding of art related to its
institutionalization. It makes much more evolutionary sense to see the
different activities that we now call art as developed out of a series of
adaptations that have provided behavioral flexibility. Activities like
storytelling develop in tandem with the radical increase of intelligence and the
ability to provide verbal representations of memorized or imagined scenarios. As
pointed out by Carroll and E. O. Wilson, whom Carroll cites, flexible
intelligence evidently had enormous adaptive advantages. A flexible
intelligence even supports inventions of recent art activities like film or
video games that run on the old bio-computer developed in the Pleistocene by
synthesizing visual, acoustic, and narrative skills. There are no special
design features in the brain developed in the EEA (Environment of Evolutionary
Adaptedness) and reserved for an art-essence, for instance film art, to be
invented many years later. Different arts and different types of a given art
activate different mental capacities, and although it is highly probable that we
could identify neurological activity typical of a given aesthetic activity, I
doubt that it is possible—as Carroll supposes—to identify neural activity
specific for aesthetic forms. Art enhances many different activities, from
strengthening social bonds to allocating special resources for perceptual
activities and thus making certain phenomena special, to borrow Ellen
Dissanayake’s term for the function of art, or serving as means of strengthening
mechanisms for imagining counterfactual situations.
Part of Carroll’s argument is aimed at
refuting the “hard” and problematic version of Pinker’s skepticism (he has
later provided softer versions) as to the adaptive value of art in general: art
is a kind of ”cheesecake” that pushes the mind’s pleasure circuits in ways
similar to drugs or pornography with no adaptive value, a kind of short-circuiting
of mental dispositions produced by natural selection to fulfill adaptive functions.
Pinker’s sharp distinction between ”just
pushing pleasure buttons” and something that is adaptive and functional is
difficult to maintain, because—a point I shall return to—it implies a
problematic distinction between “pleasure” and adaptive behavior. Cheesecake
provides you with nourishment, and environmental factors decide whether it is
adaptive for you, or whether lack of exercise and too much cheesecake make it maladaptive.
However, Pinker’s argument lures Carroll
into taking the opposite position and to forming ideas about art based on the
problematic distinction between what simply elicits pleasure and what serves higher
purposes or even causes pain. Carroll uses Freud’s distinction between the
pleasure principle and the reality principle, a distinction that deviates
radically from an evolutionary and psychological understanding. Pleasure is an
inbuilt go-mechanism aimed at motivating fitness-enhancing activities, just as
pain is an inbuilt fitness-enhancing avoidance-and-stop-mechanism (see Grodal, Moving
Pictures). There is therefore no evolutionary reason for thinking that
romance novels that articulate mating fantasies, pleasurable go-scenarios,
should in principle be more or less fitness-enhancing than stop-enhancing
tragedies that cause pain by depicting failure and death, or that even glorify
heroic suffering or martyrdom. Thoughts of death and pain may be just as
escapist or maladaptive as fantasies of mating, as any mental hospital could
demonstrate. Romances can provide illuminating mating scenarios and serve to
reinforce urges to bond. Thus, the hedonic tone of a given fiction does not per
se provide a clue as to its degree of adaptive value, it depends on the work as
well as the circumstances of the given reader or viewer. It is even not so
clear what counts as adaptive and functional in the present day environment.
What from one point of view might be evaluated as “pressing pleasure buttons” might
from another point of view seem to serve vital functions (relaxation,
reinforcement, diffusion of tension etc.).
Furthermore, Salmon’s and Symons’s claim—cited
by Carroll—that great works of art are those that most fully engage organizing
adaptations, is problematic. I know of many works of art that I would call
great for different reasons—their linguistic or visual style, the force by
which they portray given emotions, or skillfully activate counterintuitive,
supernatural phenomena—although I might think that their way of molding human
nature is maladaptive (Milton or Tarkovsky, for instance by their advocacy of
supernaturalism). There are also numerous examples of mass art that portray the
world in an adaptive way, although perhaps more examples to the contrary. To be
widely recognized as great works of art requires that the work be engage central
human concerns or central aspects of the functioning of our perceptual
dispositions, but whether the result is adaptive is a quite different problem.
High art often caters for a certain segment of the population and might have
elements that are fitness-enhancing for these segments and their function in
society as a whole. Abstract art might, for instance, enhance the ability to
concentrate and focus or enhance skills in design and communication. To enhance
communication by design is important, whether for flowers that “try to get” the
attention of bees or horticulturalists who elicit the attention of humans. But
to rank avant-garde and mass culture on a scale according to adaptive value is
problematic.
A Darwinian model explains why given
features have been selected in the past due to their fitness-enhancing
qualities in a given environment, say the EEA, and it might therefore also
explain why certain elements are selected in the present due to our biological
makeup. The human environment has changed radically since the exodus from the
Pleistocene savannas. Since the upper Paleolithic cultural explosion, radical
cultural development has taken place, but our biological nature has changed
very little. It is therefore difficult to assess whether a given feature of our
biological nature is still fitness-enhancing or has become maladaptive. The
success of violent action films and violent video games is a good illustration:
Such films make up a very substantial part of the repertoire in film, TV, and
the game world, and they certainly activate mental and emotional dispositions
such as violent coping, tribal bonding, and revenge, which were vital for the
survival of our ancestors in their environment. However, the violence and the
action performed do not correspond to typical situations for typical persons
in, say, a modern suburban world. Horror films exploit our biological
dispositions for being afraid of horrible agents with lethal teeth “out there.”
Pascal Boyer and Justin Barrett have described how such hyperactive agency
detection devices (HADD) are remnants of features that were fitness-enhancing
for our ancestors, who sought to avoid becoming a tasty lunch for predators.
However, to what extent such stories are fitness-enhancing in a modern
environment, by strengthening coping or hazard-precaution, for example, is a topic
for research.
Violent action films or horror films are
therefore not comparable to drugs that shortcut complicated mechanisms by
directly activating pleasure buttons without the kind of coping that these
mechanisms were supposed to elicit. On the contrary; the violent or
horror-inspiring fictions portray and activate behaviors that were selected in the
EEA for their fitness-enhancing aspects. Thus, even if fiction is supported by
mental mechanisms that in general are or have been fitness-enhancing, this does
not in itself provide a basis for making value judgments. Evolution is an
open-ended process, and the last 50,000 years of rapid change in our physical,
social and cultural world does not make it easier to evaluate what is adaptive
and what is not. Taking into account the EEA only explains the evolutionary
background for our present day fascinations. Evolutionary theories of
literature, film, and other arts need to avoid the naturalistic fallacy—that
is, the idea that all that is natural is for that reason good. Human nature is
made flexible to achieve fitness in changing environments, and culture is part
of those flexible control mechanisms that mold the mind within the limits of
our mental architecture.
These reservations do not diminish the need
for evolutionary theory and for a synthesis of state of the art psychology,
evolutionary theory and the humanities. Quite the contrary. As pointed out by
E. O. Wilson, Cosmides, Tooby, and Carroll, fiction in general supports
adaptive flexibility and mental organization. The better we understand the
adaptive problems raised by the radical changes that have taken place in
environment in our recent evolutionary history, the better the humanities will
be to understand and participate in our current cultural evolution. The quicker
we leave blank-slate theories behind us, and the quicker we expel the
anti-rationalistic and anti-scientific ethos of post-structuralism,
deconstructionism etc., the better. Joseph Carroll’s ‘An Evolutionary Paradigm
for Literary Studies” is a valuable contribution to a reorientation of
humanistic scholarship that reintegrates the humanities with the great family
of the sciences.
National Humanities Center
PO 12256
7 Alexander Drive
Research Triangle Park, NC 27709
gharpham@nationalhumanitiescenter.org
I am grateful to have Joseph Carroll’s
commanding summary of the state of the field of evolutionary literary study
(which I will for the purposes of efficiency baptize EVOLIST), with its
authoritative account of the fundamental premises, aims, and goals of this
emergent—emergent what? school of thought? point of view? discipline? One of
the most interesting things about EVOLIST is the fact that, without having
determined what exactly it is, it is now, on Carroll’s account, poised to flood
the market, and this at a time when many university presses are cutting back on
their lists in literary criticism. At the very least, EVOLIST is an “approach”
like Marxism, feminism, new historicism, or deconstruction; at the most, it has
ambitions to change the whole “paradigm within which literary study is now
conducted,” to “establish a new alignment among the disciplines and ultimately
to subsume all other possible approaches to literary study.” This sounds almost
apocalyptic, and Carroll’s conclusion explicitly summons up a vision of lions
and lambs; but as I will suggest below, Carroll and his colleagues might wish
to aim even higher, beyond literary study. They should, I will argue, want not
just to exploit the account of human nature now emerging from evolutionary
biology and evolutionary psychology, but to make their own contribution to the
new synthesis, giving that synthetic account what other disciplines cannot, an
explanation of the human drive to produce and consume art.
What I have described so far, and what
Carroll describes at immense length, is an undertaking distinctive for its
adaptive fitness in an academic environment. In this respect, EVOLIST can be
compared with the discipline that in many ways constitutes its direct opposite,
deconstruction. Like EVOLIST, deconstruction was both an “approach” and the end
of approaches with the advent of an ultimate truth; and like EVOLIST,
deconstruction represented itself as a form of literary study consistent with
science—not Darwinian biology, but Saussurean linguistics. And both attempt to
link literary forms with other, more empirically solid forms, cognitive in the
one case and linguistic in the other. Deconstruction was manifestly hostile to
any kind of nature, especially human nature, but it was almost unbelievably
effective in competing for scarce resources, attracting advocates and sponsors,
and in replicating itself. If it wanted a model of disciplinary fitness,
EVOLIST could do no better than deconstruction.
EVOLIST has two
competitive advantages in the form of explanations for things that routinely
stump other schools of thought. Both explanations concern value—the artistic
merit or quality of the work itself, and the value of literature to human
beings generally. The first, the question of artistic merit, has been
particularly troublesome for professional criticism. Traditional approaches
treat it either as an objective feature of the work, which can be identified
and declaimed, or as an historical fact, a social consensus with objective
markers that can be duly noted. The most common option is to treat it as a
profound but largely irrelevant mystery that lies outside the domain of what
can be usefully discussed in a scholarly setting. If I understand Carroll
correctly, EVOLIST treats literary quality as a measure of how adequately the
work registers the facts of nature, and therefore as something subject to
precise description and analysis.
On the second point, the value to human
beings of literature in general, traditional arguments have pointed to the
personal and social utility deriving from the cultivation of desirable cultural
sensitivities such as empathy and moral discrimination, or from the pleasure or
gratification we take in tracking, understanding, and appreciating formal
representational structures. According to Carroll, EVOLIST takes an entirely
different approach, one that stresses not the individual or society, but the
species. Literature, according to this approach, exercises and rewards
precisely those attributes that are most useful to us as humans struggling for
survival.
I would like to say a
few words about both promised contributions. First, literary merit. All readers
“know” that Charles Dickens is a great writer who sometimes descends to
didacticism and sentimental cliché. The death of little Nell, they understand
intuitively, is a shameless mining of sentiment that seems subliterary in its
intense emotionality; the moralizing of Hard Times is considered to be
beneath Dickens’s artistic dignity in another sense, because its polemic is too
one-dimensionally obvious to require a novel to articulate it. The mercilessly
intricate anatomy of the dark bonds of masochism, dread, shame, arrogance, and
self-hatred that tie Paul Dombey père to Edith Granger in Dombey and
Son, on the other hand, is commonly thought to represent Dickens at his
very finest. What Carroll calls “impressionistic” literary criticism might note
the contrast between these Dickensian moments, but would have no systematic
deeper account of it other than to say, for example, that sometimes Dickens
made concessions to popular taste, or that his own sensibility included an
regrettable but fortunately rarely expressed streak of vulgarity. EVOLIST would
begin the discussion by linking Dickens at his worst to the instinctual desire
for pleasure or gratification, a narcissistic indulgence in one’s own exquisite
sensations at the expense of realism or reality, and Dickens at his best to the
human capacity to transcend instinct and to confront, intellectually and
emotionally, the deeper complexities or “dissonance” of existence. This would
provide a sound basis for our intuitive value judgments, since the denial of
dissonance through the generation of pleasurable fantasies appears, from the
evolutionary perspective, not just bad art but a rejection of the very
conditions of our existence, a turning-away from reality that would, if pursued
by one and all, spell our end as a species.
And why, one might ask, do all “deeper”
truths take difficult or dissonant form? EVOLIST has an answer for that, too: it’s
our fault. The presence in the world of such a singularly powerful intelligence
as ours is the dissonance. Unlike us, other animals are instinct-driven,
and make their ways by pursuing the shortest path between two points. For them,
the immediate gratification of instinctual desire or drive is the only option
considered, and when it is achieved the mission is accomplished and they can
rest until seized by another organic impulse. We never achieve that profound
state of rest. Our freakish capacities for discerning counterfactuals,
hypotheticals, and other minds turn us into “psychological exiles,” wandering
through a world created in part by our own imaginings. The capacity to create
and appreciate representations whether they are based in reality is, in a
sense, the problem; but it is also the solution because we can deploy this
capacity to create artistic forms that mediate our experience and help us make
sense of it. This, according to EVOLIST, is what art is for. If art does not
register the human exile from nature and instinct, it not only betrays its own
nature, but fails to perform the adaptive function for the species that is its
only real justification. This is why we value more highly the difficult, the
elusive, and the contradictory even as we respond with guilty pleasure to the
cheap, the sentimental, the obvious, the regressive.
This is a powerful
explanation for what often seems important but inexplicable. I wonder, however,
if it is not at odds with its own founding hypothesis about the non-instinctive
character of human existence. If, as Carroll says, humans “do not have the
option of living outside our own imaginative constructs,” if the need for art
is “primary and irreducible,” then why should we not consider the disposition
to create and consume art an instinct, a fixed action pattern? To think of art
as a kind of unwilled behavior peculiar to the species makes art a necessary
rather than an optional feature of our existence, and creates a richer
understanding of human being as well. Our distinctiveness in the order of being
is not that we alone have the capacity to deny or defer instinct, but that our
instincts are different, more complex, productive, and genuinely creative than
those of other animals. This redescription of both art and human nature is, I
think, is a far more suggestive and even accurate notion than the one Carroll
proposes here, but I think that it is entirely consistent with the general
thrust of his thinking and may eventually turn out to be among the primary
contributions of EVOLIST to scientific understanding.
Having—if it takes my
advice—revolutionized our understanding of instinct, art, and human nature,
EVOLIST would be in an excellent position to take on another problem largely
unaddressed by traditional criticism, the value of art itself. Here the
contribution seems indisputable: the account given by Carroll of the emergent
consensus of his colleagues is powerful, clear, and convincing. The arts, he
says, “fashion an imaginative universe in which the forces at work in the
environment and inside the mind are brought into emotionally meaningful
relations to one another”; this “universe” “provides points of reference within
which humans adjust their sense of the relative value and significance of
things”; in this way, artifacts serve as “devices of behavioral orientation”
that help us understand and find our place in the world that our intelligence
makes available to us. Spiders, beavers, and birds create their homes
instinctively, and so do we. But the homes we make instinctively are not the
buildings in which we dwell, which are made by deliberation and craft. Our
instinctual home-building, EVOLIST could argue, is the creation of art.
If humanists could
respond to the often hard-edged and aggressive skepticism of legislators,
administrators, or parents concerning the value of the humanities with a rich
account of the instinctual character, and therefore the enduring necessity, of
art, they could alter the terms of the discussion. Instead of seeming “soft” by
comparison with science and technology, the humanities would be hard, or
semi-hard, because they would have not only a scientific underpinning, but
would be making their own contributions to scientific understanding. Claims for
art’s “universal” appeal would no longer seem to be based on generous
imaginings or cosmopolitan sensibilities, but would be based on a factual
understanding of human being. The humanities would have their own distinctive
contribution to make to an understanding of globalization. And rather than
seeming to represent the inessential frills of life, humanists, and especially
literary scholars, could claim in all seriousness to be in touch with the
constants in human nature, and with “the urgent needs and driving forces in
life.”
I look forward to
having such a formidable arrow in the quiver of responses to the ongoing
deterioration in the status of the humanities, and literary study in
particular. I do, however, have one reservation. Great literary criticism
impresses us with the power, richness, and responsiveness of the critic’s mind.
Reading it, we not only say, “How true!” but also, “What a genius—I would never
have seen that on my own.” Great criticism has a performative, which is to say,
an individual character that takes shape in the confrontation of a superior
mind with a powerful text. We think of “the scientific community” as having a
natural authority over the contrarian individual scientist; for the humanities,
by contrast, consensus never outfaces a brilliant individual performance, and
often serves as the ground against which the value of that performance stands
out. Will EVOLIST, in its desire to accommodate criticism to science, still be
able to generate great criticism, or will we have to surrender our appetite for
critical performance along with our primitive delight in other non-adaptive
behaviors?
For Evolutionary Criticism, Against Genetic Absolutism
Joseph Carroll’s
overview of evolutionary literary criticism and theory is lucid, wide-ranging,
and sensible. He presents a strong case for the value of an evolutionary
approach to literature. I entirely agree that evolutionary theory can make
illuminating contributions to the study of the arts (see “Laughing” and Understanding).
I hope many readers are convinced by this aspect of Carroll’s essay.
On the other hand, I
do not agree with a project of making evolutionary theory the defining approach
to literary study. Carroll states that “If evolutionary psychology can give a
true and comprehensive account of human nature, it can ultimately encompass,
subsume, or supplant the explanatory systems that currently prevail in the
humanities.” I demur from this view on many grounds. Consider, for example,
something as central to literary study as reputation. It seems clear that, say,
Shakespeare’s reputation is the result of many factors. Some involve the
possibility of making use of his work ideologically, as in the wartime
cooptation of Henry V. Some involve the political economy of publication
(e.g., the ownership of copyright--see Taylor). Some involve Shakespeare’s
incorporation into the English education system and the spread of that system
via colonialism. Some involve network factors, such that Shakespeare
connections reached a tipping point, while those for other writers did not. The
list could be extended almost indefinitely. None of these explanatory systems
is evolutionary.
Of course, an evolutionary critic could
respond that all such systems must be compatible with the results of evolution.
Ideological effects cannot operate on cognitive mechanisms that have not
evolved, for example. That is true, but trivial. It does not show us that the
evolutionary account should play a significant, not to mind “encompassing,
subsuming, or supplanting” role in explaining the ideological use of Henry V.
The same point holds for, say, physics. The ideological use of the play cannot
violate the laws of physics. That does not mean that physics contributes
significantly to explaining the ideological uses of the play.
What about a more limited project,
then—say, explaining literary universals? Carroll characterizes universals as
“cross-cultural regularities that derive from regularities in human nature.”
But universals may be produced in many ways. In consequence, our explanatory
principles should not be confined to biology. As I have discussed elsewhere
(“Non-Genetic,” “Of Universals”), cross-cultural patterns may arise from
regularities in the physical environment, recurring developmental experiences
that are not genetically programmed, emergent features of the phenomenology of
self-consciousness (Hogan, “Literature”), convergent results of group dynamics,
network patterns, etc.
My qualms about some aspects of the
evolutionary study of literature are related to the common distinction between
evolutionary psychology and Evolutionary Psychology, since much work in
evolution and literature involves not only the former, but the latter as well.
When writers refer to “evolutionary psychology,” lower case, they have in mind
a view along the following lines. The brain evolved; the mind is an emergent
system causally dependent upon the brain; thus structures, processes, and even
some contents of the mind must be open to evolutionary accounts, to the extent
that their neurological substrates are open to such accounts. In my view, this
should be uncontroversial. In contrast, when writers refer to “Evolutionary
Psychology” (EP), upper case, they have in mind a specific set of hypotheses
and a set of approaches and theoretical preferences that characterize a
particular group of researchers in evolutionary psychology, including Tooby,
Cosmides, Pinker, and others. Since I have argued against some aspects of EP
elsewhere (Cognitive), and since others have addressed these issues at
length (for example, Buller), I will not overview the topic. However, I do wish
to emphasize a few points.
First, everyone in evolutionary theory
accepts that there is a difference between mechanisms and functions. Genetic
mutation produces mechanisms—simple causal sequences, such as being frightened
by certain sorts of unexpected movement. These mechanisms are adaptive to the
degree that they approximate certain functions—for example, avoiding
dangerous things. (Note that this is not the same as the functions being
“ultimate” rather than “proximal” causes. Functions are not causes at all. The
only causes are the mechanisms.) Mechanisms never actually have these
functions. They only come more or less close to producing the same results. A
certain sort of unexpected movement may be produced by either dangerous or
benign events, but our recoil response will be triggered mechanically in either
case. Conversely, a dangerous event may or may not produce the right sort of
unexpected movement. In short, there is always some degree of mismatch between
the mechanism and the function. Again, everyone recognizes this. However,
writers in EP seem often to forget this in practice, treating the approximated
functions as if they were the mechanisms. This is why it is at best misleading
for Carroll to say that “Natural selection operates . . . so as to maximize
the chances that an organism will propagate its genes” (my emphasis). I realize
that this is probably just loose phrasing on Carroll’s part. He could explain that
it merely means “maximize relative to other options in the gene pool.” However,
this sort of loose phrasing often appears in EP writings and can have
consequences for our understanding of human psychology.
The second point I wish to emphasize is
again widely accepted by writers in EP. Adaptation is a matter of complex
systems and these systems are neurobiological. To determine just what is
adaptive and what is not, we generally need to look at the interaction of many
features, rather than considering features in isolation. Put differently, in
order for a feature to be adaptive, it needs to be adaptive in the context
of other features. Moreover, that complex of interacting features needs to
operate in accordance with the biological processes that characterize the human
brain. While acknowledging all this, EP has a tendency to consider features in
isolation from one another and from the neurological substrate. In some ways,
this is inevitable. One has to begin somewhere. On the other hand, the massive
modularity hypothesis is, in some ways, a manifestation of just this tendency.
In connection with this, it is not clear to me that the hypothesis is as
readily eliminable from EP as Carroll suggests. It may be true that writers in
EP are now less likely to affirm that modularity is massive. But it is less
clear that they have, in fact, greatly diminished their reliance on the
multiplication of distinct, pre-dedicated, functionally defined systems
(modules).
Finally, there is a tendency among writers
in EP to treat human nature as given by a set of genetically determined traits
that are more or less uniform across the species. Here, too, everyone accepts
that this need not be true. But the acceptance of this qualification in
principle does not seem to have had great effects in practice. Much of my own
work has been on literary universals (see The Mind). However, when faced
with EP writings, I often feel that they overstate universality—not so much in
assuming excessive uniformity across cultures as in assuming excessive
uniformity across individuals (e.g., in terms of kin preference or various
sorts of gender difference). I would like, therefore, to point toward some ways
in which diversity arises, even from genetic bases.
We, of course, begin with genetic predispositions.
Some of these genetic predispositions do specify traits. However, others are
better thought of in terms of parameters—options that are selected by
experience—or ranges. Language is the area in which parametric genetic
predisposition has been most thoroughly discussed. Not everyone speaks a
head-first or head-last language. That is a parameter set by experience.
Moreover, it is qualified by the setting of other parameters in specifiable
ways. Working memory provides a simple example of a range. Not all of us have
working memories of precisely the same span, though our different spans all
fall within certain limits.
In addition, the presence of a genetic
trait, parameter, or range, may be more or less constant across all people or
it may be in complementary distribution with some other feature. More simply,
even if it turns out that people generally have a certain property, it may not
be the case that everyone has that property. For example, most people have
certain sorts of left-hemisphere dominance. However, that is not entirely
uniform across the species. In some people, that form of dominance is shifted
to the right hemisphere. Moreover, there are degrees of dominance.
Again, genetic predispositions are affected
by experience. In many cases, the specific content of the experience affects
the manner in which the predisposition is expressed. There are two ways in
which this occurs—indifferently across the life span and in critical period
development. In the case of emotion, for example, emotional memories are formed
across the human life span. Emotional memories affect our emotional responses
beyond any particular, innate predispositions (e.g., they may add new fear
triggers to any that might be given genetically). More significantly, critical
period experiences form enduring propensities that are not genetically
specified as such. This may be a matter of setting parameters (as in language,
according to one account). But it need not be. For example, early childhood
experiences of parenting appear to have long-lasting effects on a person’s
tendency toward security or insecurity in attachment relations. Note that both
sorts of experiences may give rise to cultural differences, if they are uniform
within societies but different across societies, as occurs to some extent with
languages. Perhaps more consistently, they give rise to differences within
cultures, since experiences are idiosyncratic. Finally, they also give rise to
cross-cultural patterns, since some experiences are likely to occur to any
human or to at least some people in any society.
In connection with this, it is important to recognize that there are
ideological and other factors leading people to behave in ways that may go
against spontaneous dispositions. These may increase the uniformity of behavior
in ways that occlude individual diversity. Moreover, they may affect people’s
judgments about behavior (thus survey results, literary representations, etc.),
increasing the perception of uniformity. For example, suppose that literary
works consistently praise men for military accomplishment and women for beauty
and nurturance. This is what one would expect from class and gender bias in
narrative production along with class and gender ideology. It need not result
from uniform spontaneous dispositions across men and women. Indeed, if praise
is required to foster these attributes, that suggests they are not entirely
spontaneous.
In sum, evolutionary psychology is a valuable addition to literary
theory and criticism. Joseph Carroll’s essay brings out this value nicely. On
the other hand, we should not consider evolutionary psychology as some sort of
master discipline, even in the study of universals. Finally, it is important
that we recognize some of the problems with the current practice of Evolutionary
Psychology, particularly its tendency toward a sort of hyper-functionalism, its
tendency to occlude substrate complexity by multiplying discrete modules, its
tendency to present genetic predispositions as overly uniform, and its general
insensitivity to ideological effects.
24 Garfield St.
Exeter, NH 03833
(603) 770-9076
Joseph Carroll, in his
broad, hopeful panoramic snapshot, reveals a burgeoning field, albeit one at
the fringes of the literary establishment. The Literary Darwinists’ status as a
“robust guerilla band” is not necessarily a bad thing; arguably one galvanizing
force within the humanities themselves is their embattlement with respect to
mainstream culture. By this logic, literary Darwinists, doubly-embattled, ought
to work with redoubled urgency. As for evolutionary psychology itself, though,
it has already leached its way thoroughly into mainstream culture and continues
to spread like Dennett’s “universal acid.” It remains to be seen whether
Literary Darwinism can ignite the imaginations of scientists and readers, can
adequately and compellingly grasp the reasons we are continually drawn to literary
experience—to consume written stories, huddle together under their auspices to
argue or commiserate, conjure them in secret solitude or in public, get upset
and outraged by them (when they threaten religious beliefs, when they’re billed
as “true” and “exposed” as fictions). Evolutionary psychology has caught on in
the mainstream largely thanks to the way it so routinely cuts to the core of
certain aspects of human behavior. Take mating—which happens to be the title of
my favorite novel, by Norman Rush. Through EP’s lenses, parts of the eye-chart
come suddenly into sharp relief—the obsessiveness with which we pursue, agonize
over and gibber and jabber over relationships; the monstrous, betimes murderous
nature of jealousy; the prevailing folk wisdom that men and women hail from
different parts of the psychological solar system; the quirks of personal ads;
the widespread appeal of and audience for pornography; the persistence of
adultery and its temptations; the inescapable relevance of “looks”—in short, a
whole slew of phenomena that previously seemed like loosely-linked fodder for a
season of “Sex in the City” come suddenly into crystalline focus.
Does peering at
literature—at Mating rather than mating—through these lenses yield
equally dramatic insights? I’m willing to gamble on a yes, provided that
literary Darwinists remain true to their interdisciplinary spirit and enlist
the services of neuroscientists, linguists, behavioral ecologists, ethologists,
cognitive psychologists, and so forth. I’ve argued elsewhere (“By Sextants”)
for the necessity of such collaboration, but here I want to make a case for one
indispensable set of invitees to the party—actual writers, such as myself,
working in all the major literary modes: fiction, creative nonfiction, poetry,
and drama. I want to go further and argue that if we study exclusively existing
texts and ignore artists and the process by which the art comes into being,
there will be a gaping hole in the puzzle. The Literary Darwinists have an
opportunity, in their attempt to fundamentally alter the way literary study is
conducted, to bring artists into the fold, or they may miss this opportunity, I
think to the detriment of all concerned.
Currently, the relationship of so-called
“creative writers” to literary scholars is a strained one, even though there
are many who do both or who do one and aspire toward the other (I’m guessing
that there are more literary scholars who dream of writing a novel than there
are creative writers who fantasize about a definitive re-appraisal of
literature, though I could be wrong). Creative Writing programs are generally
nested within English Departments, and thus fight for the same funding and go
to the same faculty meetings and picnics. With the surge in PhD programs in
Creative Writing, as well as the number of students writing creative
dissertations, there is certainly plenty of overlap. Nevertheless, there is a
divide, marred by a mutual wariness and suspicion. Painting with broad
brushstrokes, it can be said that writers are suspicious of academic jargon and
conceptual systems that feel unwieldy, at odds with their visceral experience
of narrative, and which they believe stifle the creative process. Literary
scholars (again, broad strokes here) are in turn suspicious that creative
writers are naïve bukowskis, shunning critical thought in favor of a mystical
“writing process,” drunk on language, among other things. There is a grain of
truth, if only a grain, in these stereotypes. I’ve heard graduate students in
literature complain that the demands and conventions of scholarship detract
from the passion for reading that drove them to enroll in grad school to begin
with. And as for the artists themselves, works-in-progress are indeed messy,
amorphous, unscholarly, ungrounded in references and often lacking a sense of
literary history. Even more polished, “publishable” works haven’t yet proven
themselves anywhere close to worthy of our ongoing scrutiny in the manner of
Milton, Shakespeare, the Bröntes. Consider Harold Bloom’s The Western Canon,
with its four ages; there may be some dispute about what goes in the first
three, but even Bloom admits that as far as his “Chaotic Age,” i.e. the 20th
century, goes, his selections are highly speculative, a veritable
guessing-game. How much more chaotic, then, the work that is being saved and
backed up on a hard drive as we speak, characters springing Athena-like to life
behind their morning newspaper and coffee, or cut out of the universe on
instinct and whim, provisional endings to meet deadlines, scenes to be excised,
rearranged, points of view upended, key lines of dialogue yet to be inserted
because the writer has yet to overhear them in the café with Tobias Wolff’s
voice echoing in his head? In short, creative writing is horridly messy and incorrigibly
contingent, as any honest writer will fess up, yet in the end it’s where the
stuff comes from.
As a fiction writer,
it is not with the “production of new knowledge” that I am concerned, but with
the generation of new stories, broadly speaking, and more specifically with the
generation of new characters, new situations, new words and word-strings, new
rhythmic and sonic possibilities, new ways of examining the world—perceiving
it, challenging it, rearranging it, and making my way in it. Yet no matter how
outlandish the situations, no matter how oblique or experimental or allusive
the prose gets, some connection remains in it to basic underlying human wants,
needs, and motivations. Even Finnegans Wake, pushing the edges of
comprehensibility, might be partly decoded through an understanding of dreams,
which themselves may be understood at least partly as a neuropsychological
phenomenon in relation to waking states, as in the work of J. Allan Hobson (Thirteen
Dreams). As neuropsychological events, dreams are subject to evolutionary
explanations as is any behavior. This would be a good case of where an
interdisciplinary approach is necessary if the exploration of the subject is to
be fruitful. Further, it ought to remind us that in the most radical, formally
and stylistically innovative text or meta-fiction, the evolutionary-minded can
and ought to weigh in.
So much the more so
for more conventional forms of contemporary writing, which still, lo and
behold, rely on characters (!) in settings (!) who face conflicts (!), undergo
events, and arrive at some resolution, however open to interpretation the
latter may be. Those basic technical terms, which have persisted in creative
writing since its inception as a “discipline,” might sound simplistic next to differénce,
deixis and their ilk, but they are the working writer’s toolkit. It also
happens that they dovetail rather nicely with many evolutionary, cognitive, and
neuroscientific concepts. Writers, for instance, talk unabashedly about their
“characters,” and tend to think of them as individuals. Carroll underscores a
point which should be glaringly obvious but isn’t—that “motivations, actions,
and interpretive responses all originate in the neurological events in
individual brains,” and that “novelists and playwrights are individual persons
who construct intentional meanings about those characters.” Sage advice it is
at the outset of the storywriting process to develop a verbal character-sketch.
Once one has rendered a someone that piques one’s interest enough, a
concatenation of traits and circumstances worth running ahead with, then
allow the plot to emerge. In evolutionary psychology, in spite of controversies
about group selection, the dominant paradigm has it that the phenotypic
individual is the entity directly subject to selection pressures. Without
suggesting that poststructuralist, historical and culture-centered theory have
nothing to offer to writers, how refreshing to find a field that argues
strenuously for individual selves. When our characters hound and haunt us at
our desks, when we grow to care about them, when they seem to wrest control
from us and take charge of their own destinies, maybe we aren’t being merely
naïve and delusional; maybe such phenomena reveal something important about literature.
When it comes to
conflict, writers also find sympathetic ears from the Literary Darwinists. It
is a truism that for a story to be compelling and take wing, conflict is the
engine that drives the narrative—it’s not enough for everything to be okay,
pretty and wonderful. Darwinism insists on a universe teeming with conflict on
a variety of levels, more interesting and variegated than either those of
tooth-and-claw caricature or those of Dr. Freud. To cite examples,
parent-offspring conflict and sibling rivalry are explained by evolutionary
thinking as a natural outgrowth of psychological factors given the algorithmic
logic of survival demands under conditions that would have persisted from the
EEA to today. Parents and their offspring, crudely, have overlapping interests
but also distinct and competing ones, conscious and otherwise. The same applies
to siblings. And evolutionary psychology has shown us most appositely why men
and women are drawn into a continuous dance of attraction and rejection, admiration
and hostility, thanks to distinct psychological mechanisms that are a
consequence of different fitness demands. In short, evolutionary thinking
reveals a world where conflict runs rampant, and just as creative writers can
benefit from appreciating the underlying sources of such conflicts,
evolutionary thinkers can learn from the types of conflicts in literature that
“work,” that fulfill some inner need, those which tweak our pleasure circuits
or get under our skin.
There are plenty of
other concepts that I could adduce from Carroll’s work and elsewhere which
continue this theme that writers and evolutionary-minded literary thinkers have
a lot of common ground. I could talk about life-history theory and the stories
of Alice Munro, which often trace the decisions her characters make over the
course of lifetimes. I could discuss Geoffrey Miller’s fitness displays and the
gaudy linguistic fireworks of David Foster Wallace—Miller’s theory need not
apply equally to all artistic endeavors to have some validity. I could connect
the work Lisa Zunshine is doing with Theory of Mind to the writer’s mantra to
“show rather than telling” or the gentle art of ending effectively, the subtle
implication that much more sublime than the point hammered home. But I’d rather
close by bringing things back to why literary critics in general, and thus
Literary Darwinists in particular, ought to seek out the company of writers.
At least in my
lifetime, literary study has taken place as if texts came straight off the
shelves in Borges’s Library of Babel, natural and/or cultural objects to be
scrutinized, critiqued, understood, and so forth. The mind, body, and life of
the writer (with some exceptions, feminists among the dissenters) have been
deemed irrelevant at best, and at worst distracting. Yet, is it crazy to
suggest that the minds of writers—their imaginations, motivations, ways of
approaching and solving problems, and so forth, might be helpful, even crucial,
to investigate? Our knowledge is growing, as amply documented by Carroll, about
the relationship between characters in literature and actual behavior, about
how art reconceives such behavior, about art’s role in human behavior, whether
it is adaptive or not, etc. Through Literary Darwinist lenses, we may even have
begun to understand readers and texts better than ever before. But as for the
unkempt, at once exhilarating and agonizing endeavor of inventing characters
and scenarios and bringing them to some end, satisfactory or otherwise,
literary critics and scientists alike as yet know very little. Will the
Literary Darwinists, along with their neurocognitive brethren, take the time to
find out more?
Joseph Carroll’s essay, “An Evolutionary
Paradigm for Literary Study,” gives us a solid overview of evolutionary
psychology and literary study. In my response I will address a few major points
in hopes of spurring yet more written conversation.
Carroll wants to
institute, not just
another paradigm, but in fact the
paradigm for literary study. (More specifically, he wants to undo the
continuing reign of poststructuralist-derived theory.) A Darwinian approach, he
writes, should “ultimately…subsume all other approaches to literary study.”
Taking this even further: ‘if evolutionary psychology can give a true and
comprehensive account of human nature, it can ultimately encompass, subsume, or
supplant the explanatory systems that currently prevail in the humanities” in
general. On the one hand this seems true. If the brain is the result of natural
selection, and if the mind is a function of the brain, then evolutionary
psychology would seem to be a rock-bottom explanatory paradigm for all things
mental. But on the other hand this fact does not justify the kind of necessity
that Darwinian critics often want to establish.
Carroll wants to make
the case that any literary-interpretive practice that does not overtly stake
itself on evolutionary-psychological theory will be at least inadequate, if not
simply invalid. Even work that emphasizes cognitive-scientific ideas over
evolutionary-psychological ideas does not pass muster. For instance, Carroll
rejects attempts to theorize a ‘cognitive poetics’ that is not plainly also
evolutionary psychology. “Efforts to segregate cognitive poetics from evolutionary
literary study are doomed to failure.” This is necessarily the case, he claims,
because the “human mind has functional cognitive mechanisms for precisely the
same reason that the human organism has complex functional structures in other
organ systems—because it has evolved through an adaptive process by means of
natural selection.” Of course it’s true that knowing the ultimate function of
an object of investigation matters for fully understanding the nature of that
object. But I don’t see how it follows that all discussions of that object must
feature a discussion of its ultimate function; and in particular why a
discussion of whatever element of a living organism must feature a discussion
of evolution. Would this also mean, for instance, that a non-evolutionary
explanation of the way the liver works is doomed to failure?
Carroll’s comments on
Lisa Zunshine’s use of Theory of Mind (ToM) in her Why We Read Fiction make this even clearer. “Despite her
appeal to selected bits of evolutionary psychology,” he writes, “Zunshine
strongly emphasizes the ‘cognitive’ aspect of her views, muting and minimizing
their sociobiological affiliations. Beyond ‘ToM,’ she declines to attribute any
very specific structure to the adapted mind.” As Carroll admits, Zunshine does
not ignore evolutionary psychology; still, by not making it the focus of her
work, she has segregated herself from the
explanation that matters. But Theory of Mind is an element of our cognitive
apparatus whether or not we discuss it directly in terms of evolution.
Zunshine’s book—based on the notion that ‘cognitive psychology’ and
‘evolutionary psychology’ are not simply different names for the same
thing—chooses to make the case about the specific cognitive function(s) of ToM
in relation to fiction. To fault examples of cognitive literary study as
Carroll does here is, as Lawrence Shapiro observes, to be “overly zealous” in
“applying evolutionary theory to psychological questions” (253).
For literary study
that in no way includes evolutionary psychology, the situation is worse, for
Carroll seems to take it that leaving out evolution will necessarily render a
given explanation somehow false. We see this when he addresses the recurrent
question of whether the Darwinists have actually produced any new readings of
literature. Carroll claims that the real question is: “Can the Darwinists produce formulations that are not only new but true?”:
the implication being that the other side is constantly making new, but false,
claims. There are at least two responses to this. First, it’s hard to
see how any new paradigm can succeed if it does not generate new knowledge.
Second, it is possible to make valid claims in spite of beginning from false or
incoherent grounding positions. Many post-structuralist-derived
literary-critical claims about the unconscious operations of race, class, and
gender, for instance, have been straightforwardly true of our actual world,
whether or not their understanding of human nature is valid.
I want to be clear
that I’m not saying professional scholars should be satisfied to make claims
based on false logical grounds. They should not. To my mind any serious scholar
should be willing and able to deal seriously with the most serious challenges
to his or her own positions. But if such challenges are to stand a chance of
being seriously attended to, it will matter how they are made. Carroll tends
regularly to overstate his case, and this works to antagonize the very audience
he most wants to persuade.
I turn now to another
issue—anthropomorphism—which is a regularly occurring problem with
evolutionary-psychological approaches to literary study. Darwinism is
revolutionary because of its incorporation of chance and determinism. The
always mind-wrenching, originary fact is that the order of life happened by
chance. In the most general event-scenario, a random genetic mutation occurs in
an organism; and if by chance the environment favors the outcome of that
mutation, then that mutation will have a likelihood of becoming part of a
changed order of living things. The process, like all natural processes, is
entirely mechanistic. Given this foundational fact, we must constantly be on
our guard not to impute some anthropomorphic, decision-making power to nature.
And yet this regularly happens.
I’ll consider two
quick, related examples: design and problem-solving. Carroll, like so many
other writers on evolution, speaks of “the adaptive problem [a given]
behavioral disposition would have solved in ancestral environments.” Even more
telling is phrasing about “the adaptive problem these complex structures [ie,
the arts] are designed
to solve” (italics added). Now, the idea of ‘design’ has always been
necessarily contentious in evolutionary theory, because we have to speak of
order arising by chance. In my opinion we should not use the word ‘design’
because in normal usage it entails a conscious designer, and these normative
entailments of specific words matter, especially in the context of evolutionary
theory. We see this also with the idea of evolution as ‘problem-solving.’ To
characterize evolution as a problem-solving process is necessarily to assume
some unproblematic, right kind of being toward which the natural process must
be moving. In fact it assumes what I have to see as a covert form of intelligent
design. Of course it is hard not to use our everyday words, and therefore hard
not to anthropomorphize in this way. But, again, especially in the context of
explaining culture and psychology in terms of evolution, this kind of usage
needs to be avoided, or at least qualified.
With anthropomorphism
we have a case of natural processes being understood as if they were somehow
human in a general sense. Now we turn to a case of elements of nature being
understood as if they were elements of a specific culture. This tendency shows up when Carroll
makes the key generalization that literature “embodies an intuitive folk
psychology at its highest level of articulation.” What is the standard by which
such a judgment can be made? From what neutral, non-culturally-biased
perspective could we assess—actually we would be evaluating—a given
articulation of folk psychology as higher or lower than another? Why wouldn’t
the visual arts be highest? With respect to literature in particular, as soon
as we make such a judgment, we automatically institute a similar kind of
evaluation with respect to specific examples of literature. If literature is
the highest articulation of folk psychology, then there will necessarily be
some examples of literature that more highly articulate that psychology than do
others. To make claims like this is to read, unwittingly I assume, natural
phenomena as cultural phenomena. Darwinists deeply undercut their own authority
if they fail to realize, or at least to acknowledge, when they are doing this.
To this point I have
addressed what I take to be crucial, if largely rhetorical, problems that are
common both to Carroll’s essay and to the interdisciplinary use of evolutionary
psychology more generally. Now I’ll address a more substantive issue. Carroll
wants to make the case for the adaptive nature of the arts, and of literature
in particular. To this end, he turns to ideas put forth by E. O. Wilson in Consilience. Both Wilson and
Carroll claim that the arts appeared in human life because of a downside to the
evolution of our specifically human intelligence. Higher intelligence enabled
the human animal to detach itself from purely automatic, instinctive responses
to the world, and to deal with “contingent circumstances and hypothetical
situations” in ways that no other creature can. But the proliferation of
‘mental scenarios’ detached from instinct produces a potential chaos in
organizing motives and regulating behavior. The arts produce images of the
world and of our experience in the world. Those images mediate our behavior and
the elemental passions that derive from human history. The arts are thus an
adaptive response to the adaptive problem produced by the adaptive capacities
of high intelligence.
In another phrasing we read that the “disposition
for creating [literary] images would have solved an adaptive problem that, like
art itself, is unique for the human species: organizing motivational systems
disconnected from the immediate promptings of instinct.” Now, unless I just
entirely misunderstand, I don’t see how this could reasonably explain the
ultimate function of literature and the arts. We have an initial evolutionary
change: the increase of intelligence. But that intelligence cannot function
without what comes after it: the arts. So, without the arts the change in
intelligence will evidently have no organization, or at least not the kind of
organization that will make it functional. In fact disorganized, proliferating
mental scenarios sounds to me like a state of dream or hallucination. How could
such a change ever be adaptive in the first place? How could such a creature
ever effectively deal with the world at all? How can this be squared with any
usual notion of cause and effect? Carroll seems to be aware of this problem
later when he writes that the “capacity for producing emotionally charged
imaginative artifacts developed in tandem with the capacity for producing an
imaginative virtual world.” Now, we have intelligence and its organization
happening, not in sequence, but at the same time. I still don’t see how this
could work.
To conclude, I’ll say
that I feel fairly confident about my comments on anthropomorphism and
value-judgments. But in criticizing Carroll’s explanation of the adaptive
function of art, I wonder if I have gone past my own knowledge. Maybe I just
don’t know the evolutionary-psychological theory well enough to understand what
Carroll, who is much more broadly-educated in evolutionary psychology than I
am, actually intends. This is an unavoidable risk in getting involved in
interdisciplinarity. But of course Carroll has taken on the much larger risk. A
scholar who crosses disciplinary lines as he has done, risks not only failing
to know the other field (evolutionary psychology) adequately enough to satisfy
scholars in that other field, but also of failing to explain ideas from the
other field in such a way that the relatively un-educated in his or her own
original field (literary studies) can understand them. One way or the other a
significant portion of both audiences must be satisfied if there is to be a
successful interdiscipline.
To conclude, whether
or not the new paradigm emerges as Carroll hopes, I am glad that there are
scholars like him, who are willing to take these kinds of risks.
Evolutionary Psychology and Literary Studies
TU Darmstadt, Germany
In the cognitive sciences and evolutionary psychology there are now
complex models of human nature on offer, and it is a frequently-discussed
question whether these models can be made useful for the humanities too.[37] One
of the central issues in this debate is the question of whether there is
something like a definable human nature at all or just a blank slate ready to
be shaped by totally different forms of culture. Obviously humans are not
determined in their behaviour by the clear cut genetic programs found in many
animals. Does this mean that human behaviour is not determined at all by any
genetic disposition? Is the only biological heritage humans have – in relation
to their behaviour and the way their minds operate – a boundless plasticity for
culture? The evidence brought forward in the last few years has caused many
observers to assume that the answer to this question is ‘no’. Most models
explaining the evidence agree on the point that in the course of evolution
humans adapted to culture and in ontogeny humans need culture in order to
develop, while culture in itself is always evolving. Therefore we can speak of
a coevolution of biological dispositions and human culture. In contrast to
Joseph Carroll (“Human Nature and Literary Meaning”) it seems to me that it is
still very unclear what kind of human universals there are, and how their
interaction with culture can be modelled; likewise, it is uncertain how the
interaction between dispositions, cultural traditions and individual variances
of dispositions, and of the experience of culture, ultimately comes together.
Nevertheless everyone interested in human culture is asked to take these
assumptions about human nature into account and that includes humanists who are
interested in the study of art and literature.
Joseph Carroll considers that the best way of doing this is to include
art in the set of phenomena explained by evolutionary psychology. In his view
art has to fulfil an adaptive function – therefore it can be explained by
evolutionary psychology – and he defines three criteria which any explanation
has to satisfy:
“(a) Define art in a
way that identifies what is peculiar and essential to it – thus isolating the
behavioural disposition in question; (b) identify the adaptive problem this
behavioural disposition would have solved in ancestral environments; and (c)
identify design features that would efficiently have mediated this solution.”
(Carroll 14 [please
insert the correct page number]).
In the following I
will argue that (1) his basic assumption, that art fulfils an adaptive
function, is problematic and (2) therefore the function he ascribes to
evolutionary psychology has to be reconsidered.
(1) The adaptive function of art
Talking about the adaptive function of art presupposes that there is
something like ‘art’: not a culturally specific set of activities grouped by
this culture under one label and understood as belonging together, but
something which can be seen on the analytical level as an activity or a set of
activities all conforming to one definition. Carroll proposes such a
definition: [Art is] “the disposition for creating artefacts that are
emotionally charged and aesthetically shaped in such a way that they evoke or
depict subjective, qualitative sensations, images, or ideas.” I am not sure why
Carroll is talking about the ‘disposition for creating artefacts’ and not the
artefacts themselves, because obviously they are at the centre of his
definition. On a closer view it becomes clear that it is a very broad
definition and encompasses many artefacts we do not usually classify as art,
like the speeches of ancient orators, the Christian cross, advertisements, the
ceremonies at baroque courts, cars or haircuts, to name just a few.
In the text following his definition Carroll cites studies which see
humans as a ‘story-telling species,’ or see a ‘species-typical need for finding
and making meaning’ prototypically found in the rhythmic and emotionally
modulated interactions of mothers and infants, or see stories as a means to
organize our lives, etc. He tries to keep this fast expanding little universe
together by claiming that “narrative and verse and emotionally modulated
musical and visual patterns” are really “design features” of art. Actually this
is a strong claim. It is one thing to argue that we find stories where we find
humans – which is really an empirical question – but it is a totally different
claim to link this story-telling capacity and need to a general module called art
with its own adaptive function.
So in my opinion there are two problems with Carroll’s definition:
first, the general definition of art is too wide and unspecific, and second,
the activities and capacities he sees as design features are not part of art by
any empirical argument but rather by our contemporary understanding of art. It
is common knowledge that ‘art’ (Shiner) or ‘literature’ (Wellek) are
comparatively new concepts. Many activities and texts which are nowadays
understood as self-evidently classified into these rather abstract categories would
have been viewed as different and unconnected in earlier times. This historical
argument doesn’t imply that it is impossible to find something which all
entities nowadays classified as art or literature have uniquely in common, but
it becomes obvious that this is rather an improbable project. The concept of
art is so abstract that objects in very different media are classified under
this label, like pictures or sculptures, movies and photographs, dance and
music. The same is true for literature, which subsumes texts written to be read
alone (like most novels from the 20th century; texts meant to be
performed, like songs and plays; texts which are strictly metrically organized;
and texts which have no metrical organisation at all, etc). The perception and
processing of these artefacts is based on different senses and demands very
different abilities. It is the result of our cultural history that we subsume
all these different artefacts under one label. The way Carroll takes literature
to be a form of art is a product of this history. To assume that this complex
concept is not only a modern institution bundling together very different
activities and artefacts, but at the same time something that re-establishes an
order which had been formed 100,000 years ago when art was supposedly formed as
an adaptive module, is quite a leap of faith. Someone who bases his argument on
the assumed unity of this concept has quite a burden of proof – a proof which
in Carroll’s essay, with his expansive definition of art, is missing. In short:
there is no adaptive function of art or literature because these are modern
concepts. Carroll and other Darwinian literary critics have still to make a
convincing argument that there is a definition of these concepts which can be
applied to all human cultures, and one which is not an anachronistic
projection.
In this perspective it seems much more plausible to decouple specific
adaptions and these modern concepts. Then we can assume that there are
adaptions like an organizational mode for human abilities or a scope syntax
(Tooby and Cosmides, “Does Beauty Build?”) and a cultural evolution in which
the organisational mode for some abilities is the basis for our aesthetic
appraisal in the context of art, while others are classified as sports, others
as games, etc.
(2) The function of evolutionary psychology in literary studies
Even if there is no
adaptive function of art we shouldn’t assume that art or literature – and I
will concentrate on the latter – is an independent realm untouched by those
aspects of ‘human nature’ evolutionary psychology is discussing. On the
contrary, we have to assume that most aspects of literature in some way or
other relate to genetic dispositions acquired in the process of evolution. How
do humans process signs, how do they attribute intentions, etc.? Organizing
information in the form of story telling, for example, seems to be a good
candidate for such an explanation, as are the other ‘design features’ Carroll
discusses. So generally I agree with Carroll’s claim that literary studies
depend in many ways on anthropological assumptions. We need these assumptions
or models on which we base our understanding of texts. In other words a theory
of interpretation, for example, interfaces with a general theory of human
language and sign usage, with a theory of attributing human intentions, etc.
But this doesn’t really answer the question of what role evolutionary
psychology can play in literary theory. Carroll views it as the most important
discipline for us, which I doubt for a couple of reasons:
1)
Evolutionary psychology doesn’t
offer specific theories which are crucial for literary theory. Whether human
language use is based on a specific grammar module or not is not important for
evolutionary psychology, because it is compatible with both positions – and,
more importantly, it doesn’t have a language theory of its own. The same is
true for sign use.
2)
Most aspects of evolutionary
psychology are relevant for literary theory in two ways: a) as part of a
general anthropological framework, b) to explain the fascination of literary
themes and motives which can be found in different cultures and times. But I
cannot see how to apply it to the study of a single text. A literary text is
first of all an intentional artefact and even if the ability to read intentions
is the result of an evolutionary adaption, the procedure of reading the
intention and the content of these intentions depends very heavily on cultural
knowledge (so much so, indeed, that it is easier to ignore the fact that this
ability is a human universal and to make successful use of it all the time – as
much of the humanities are doing at the moment – than the other way around).
3)
A practical reason: Evolutionary
psychology is in itself a complex and fast evolving research field and it is
impossible to have a firm grasp of it in its current and developing state and
be a specialist in literary studies at the same time. If one aims at doing more
in one’s own research field than to popularize evolutionary psychology to a
specific group of scholars one has to organize the way the information
interchange between the two fields is managed. One way would be to rely on the
stabilized information alone which can be found in handbooks, which isn’t a
very useful approach for new research fields. Another way is to insert a level
of abstraction which describes something in a domain independent language and
is compatible with the state of knowledge in evolutionary psychology. For
example one can describe the way intention is at work in human language usage
using concepts from Grice (Studies) or Sperber’s and Wilson’s relevance
theory (Relevance) and this can be seen as compatible with an
evolutionary account.[38]
So I advocate the use
of evolutionary psychology not as a research paradigm but as a framing theory.
Even then it is very useful and quite important, as are other results from
cognitive science. Including the theory of mind, for example, in research on
literary phenomena totally changes the discussion of character, which has been
dominated by anti-mimetic attitudes, or of authorial intentions, where literary
theory has been dominated by anti-intentionalist stances while the practice was
and is a wild mix of intentionalist and anti-intentionalist arguments.
Attaining compatibility with the findings of the human sciences is the least we
can, and should, expect to achieve in literary studies.
This is true even if most of the main content of our subject area cannot
be understood using the tools of evolutionary psychology. This seems to me
especially the case for the analysis of intentions. The content of an intention
can even go against everything we know about human abilities and limits. So if
an author devises a novel which can be read in its entirety in twenty-four
hours, and which tells a story covering the same length of time in such a way
that the ideal reader has to have a perfect memory to understand and resolve
all intra- and intertextual relations, we can safely assume that an empirical
test would show us that very few readers are able to read the novel in that
way. But as textual scholars we are usually not so much interested in what
readers really do with a text but what the texts want them to do. This is in no
way meant to deprecate the empirical study of literature, which is an important
field of social science, but to lump it together with the completely different
field of literary studies as Carroll does seems to me to be a category error.
Empirical analysis of texts using text mining procedures or stylometry can be a
useful strategy in literary studies because the object of research is not the
empirical reader but the text.
All this critique aside, Carroll’s essay is one of his many
contributions to redesigning literary studies in such a way that it is
compatible with the human sciences and incorporates their knowledge into our
field of research. To my mind this is much more fruitful than all these
attempts to establish culture as an area totally independent of human history –
because that it what evolution is also about.
Complex Realities, Adequate Reductions
A Reply to Joseph Carroll.
Let us suppose, because we have good reason
to, that everything that exists and happens on this earth has natural causes.
If true, this supposition rules out ontological discontinuities in the process
of hominization and in the evolution of human culture. Joseph Carroll wants us
to believe that this conclusion is a privileged insight—indeed, a distinguishing
mark—of the neo-naturalist turn he envisions for the humanities. It is not.
Excluding supernatural explanations from rational inquiries is the foundational
operation of all post-theological scholarship and science. Hence, naturalist
and culturalist methodologies in the humanities rarely disagree about human
culture’s basic dependence on natural givens. What they disagree about are the
epistemological implications of this dependence.
Joseph Carroll’s essay is a good example of
how neo-naturalists tend to frame this disagreement. According to the
underlying logic of Carroll’s argument, the natural existence of human beings
(“human nature”) requires us to understand culture—i.e., human reflections on,
and modifications of, their natural needs, capacities, and environments—as a
linear derivation of our animal nature: a derivation that has little, if any,
qualitative impact on the natural processes it is otherwise able to objectify.
Thus, whoever argues that human culture has produced environments and life-ways
whose complexity is frequently at odds with the first, pre-cultural mode of
nature from which they evolved risks being termed a supernaturalist. In a more
polite but no less severe binary, literary Darwinists like to describe their
critics as “traditional humanists,” “epistemological and metaphysical dualists,”
or idealistic celebrators of “the spiritual power of humanistic experience.”
Following a critical essay on neo-naturalist theory and practice, I myself was labeled
an “aesthete” by Karl Eibl. In the said essay and the ensuing debate with Eibl,
I laid out my reservations concerning the kind of research program now
summarized by Carroll.[39] I
will not repeat the particulars of my critique here but shall concentrate on
one single issue raised by Carroll: the issue of reductionism.
Neo-naturalists typically feel that
reductionism is the major charge leveled against them by “traditional
humanists.” So they think that if this charge can be neutralized, all external
opposition is bound to collapse. Much rhetorical force is therefore invested in
branding reductionism as a taboo argument that betrays the theoretical naivety
of those who bring it up. Reductionism, we are told (and rightly so), is not a
bad word in the theory of science and scholarship because any type of rational
knowledge in one way or another seeks to reduce observed phenomena to
“underlying regularities” (Carroll) or to an anterior level of argument in a
logical system of description. So far, so true. Does it follow that all types
of rational reduction provide apt knowledge about the thing thus reduced?
Carroll himself is doubtful: in traditional humanist criticism and in
postmodern criticism (his chief adversaries), he identifies certain “thematic
reductions,” of which he seems to disapprove. In both cases, Carroll observes,
literary characters appear as “allegorical embodiments” of humanist norms or of
key terms within the respective “source theories.” Apparently, then, Carroll distinguishes
between good and bad forms of reductionism—and the criterion of distinction is
whether a given reduction produces adequate knowledge or not. In the
same manner, Carroll addresses scientists whose philological speculations he
finds insufficient and notes that their theories “fail to give an adequate account
of [their] subject”: “the arts cannot adequately be reduced to didactic lessons
and pleasurable fantasy.” And toward the end of his essay, when we read that both
groups—scientists and philologists—need to learn from the other paradigm,
Carroll speaks of “concepts and modes of thinking characteristic of the
humanities and appropriate to them” (my emphasis).
I sympathize with Carroll’s insistence on
mutuality in interdisciplinary endeavors, and I consider as crucial his concern
with appropriate reductions. But I believe that this principle needs to
be applied to neo-naturalist approaches as well. If done so, the field surveyed
by Carroll begins to look a good deal less exciting than its practitioners like
to claim. In fact, judged by their own standards and ambitions, neo-naturalist
approaches have been rather unsuccessful in their campaign to “ultimately
encompass, subsume, or supplant the explanatory systems that currently prevail
in the humanities” (as Carroll predicts). If bio-philology so far has been
unable to deliver on such promises, this is not because the field is still
young and beginnings are always modest, but because most of those promises are
immodestly unrealistic. Alarmingly, even the more humble projects risk failure
as long as they do not confront their methodological self-involvement and their
tendency towards institutional partisanship.
Concerning methodological self-involvement,
Carroll leaves little doubt that he prefers a maverick type of naturalism to
one that would try to integrate its perspective within “currently prevailing”
culturalist approaches. This is so because Carroll and other contributors to The
Literary Animal regard those established approaches as diametrically
opposed to their own. They claim that the prevailing methods in the humanities
are marred by “constructivist” stances, which allegedly “attribute exclusive
shaping power to culture.” Social constructivists, in other words, deny the
existence of human nature. Carroll and his fellow combatants never consider if
their chosen antagonists have already transcended the dichotomous distinction
of nature and culture that is so troublesome to neo-naturalists—or whether they
are at least trying to do so, and this in a manner highly appropriate to their
objects of research. For while literary Darwinists want to get rid of the
nature/culture divide by effectively collapsing the concept of culture into the
concept of nature, constructivists more often than not attempt to do justice to
the unique, hence distinct, traits and regularities that set this realm of
existence apart from all other natural orders, without positing an ontological
rupture.
Of course, Carroll does not deny that human
culture is a special part of the natural world and that it requires special
tools of description and understanding. “Most human interactions,” he writes,
“are organized within cultural systems, and cultural systems profoundly
influence most individual experience.” There are consequences to be drawn and
taken from this insight. I am not sure if our current biologists are willing to
draw and take them. At the very least, it would be worth recognizing that the
“profound influences” of “cultural systems” are exactly what cultural studies
methodologies, even with poststructuralist pedigrees, are interested in. Far
from denying that culture is an evolved part of nature (albeit one that in turn
affects the reality of natural processes), those methodologies have been
working hard to develop research tools and descriptive systems that are appropriate
to the distinctiveness of their objects.
We could enter now into an extended debate
on what constitutes adequate knowledge about human culture. Elsewhere, I have
tried to outline some basic thoughts on this question.[40] At
this point, I merely want to emphasize that all such knowledge needs to
acknowledge that human culture emerges from what neuroscientists call “meta-representations.” While being part of nature, humans are
capable of reflecting on their own natural existence and even on these acts of
reflection themselves. I maintain that the reality and results of such meta-representations
require us to complicate the application of evolutionary principles to issues
of human inter-subjectivity and human history. Undoubtedly, one can question
the utility of this or that postmodern theory in this regard as well. But this
need not stop us from analyzing culture as “a historical process of
differentiation, involving intentions, non-intended determinations of
intentions, misunderstandings, appropriations, and contingencies” (Kelleter,
“Tale” 176). Contemporary cultural theory illustrates that we can do so without
resorting to supernatural or metaphysical explanations. So, while I share
Carroll’s uneasiness about the vagueness of much humanist scholarship today, I
feel that any alternative research program needs to enter into a serious
dialogue with established approaches that have been dealing with these issues
for quite some time now. Instead of dismissing them as anti-scientific, simply
because interpretive methods are part of their tool kit, one can perhaps learn
something from their interest in human representations and conceptualizations
of nature. Bio-philologists, for instance, could clarify for themselves what
image of nature informs their own data discussions.
Joseph Carroll, for one, subscribes to a
paradigm that sees nature as “an unbroken chain of
material causation from the lowest level of subatomic particles to the highest
levels of cultural imagination.” I am not a scientist, but based on my studies
of cultural and literary history, it seems unlikely to me that a causal chain model
of culture is able to replace systemic network models of culture, as they are
suggested by advanced social and praxeological theories in the humanities (from
Pierre Bourdieu to Niklas Luhmann, their individual limits notwithstanding). It
seems unlikely to me that a linear chain model can replace such object-attuned
studies in complexity, because the most complex natural object on this earth
itself seems unfit for structural explanations of a straightly causal kind.
Neuroscientists have just begun to conceptualize the human brain as a social
organ of unique “plasticity”: a biological organ
structurally receptive to environmental changes, including human actions,
communications, and artifacts. Already, these investigations suggest that the
brain in its higher cognitive functions (i.e., in those functions that are
pivotal to the process of hominization) has no center of operational
congruence, no hub of linear distribution. Why would human culture be
adequately reducible to unified causal explanations, if the human brain is not?
From what I understand, the neuronal construction of individual knowledge in
its most advanced forms does not occur through hierarchical chain reactions but
through parallel processing, self-organizing structuration, and often
unanticipated feedback loops.[41] Add
to this the emergence of human culture, not as the causal result of neuronal
activities within individual brains but as the systematic result of interactions
between human brains, and it becomes difficult to think of
meta-representations as something other than structure-building communications,
not only in the brains involved but in the complex system of culture at large.
To put it less abstractly, humans alone
among species can communicatively shape and to a certain extent become the
environmental factors that express their biological dispositions. Humans are
not only able to gather individual information about the world and to share
this information with other members of the species, but these acts of information-sharing
can reach self-awareness. By this, they become acts of making meaning: they bring
into existence a self-organizing, self-developing system of information called
culture, which amazingly lacks a nervous system of its own. Among all social
orders in the natural world, human culture is exceptional because it allows
information to be redirected and systematized through contact with other
observers and reflectors; it allows knowledge to be discussed, modified,
organized, interpreted, and stored outside individual brains, making possible
self-critique, role play, social and gender identities, imagination and
performance, thought and emotion experiments, and competing cultures in the
plural (rather than just rivaling populations). In this sense, humans are
capable of transcending their animal nature without becoming unnatural. It has
always been tempting to idealize this capacity of communicative
self-objectification by ascribing a divine cause or a metaphysical telos to it.
Carroll’s discontent with such idealisms is well founded. But theories that
seek to replace complex accounts of culture with explanations of “a single,
unified causal structure” are badly equipped for the task at hand.[42]
Like ever so many 19th-century novels, they find consolation in
describing the human species as basically just another animal. In so doing, neo-naturalists
certainly find something that is “there” (and in this sense “true”)—but their single, unified truth keeps missing the point.
This is why zoomorphic readings of
literature are often so disappointing, despite their methodological
sophistication. It is not their reductionism that is bothersome but their way
of being reductive. Just like the postmodern master theories criticized, for
example, Darwinian approaches tend to read literary texts as allegories of
themselves, always discovering that this or that novel, poem, or drama is
really about basic biological universals (mate selection, physical
survival, status fights, etc.). And while all of this is true in some way—in
fact, it would be surprising if such elements were lacking in narratives
produced by humans—these basic insights remain spectacularly incapable of explaining
the (historical, cultural, aesthetic) complexities that constitute our objects
of research when we study culture. “Human females,” Carroll writes, “are . . .
distinctive in having menopause and thus a period of life that extends beyond
the reproductive years. That period enables older women to raise their latest
offspring to maturity and to aid in caring for grandchildren.” While this rings
convincingly in evolutionary terms, it illustrates that evolutionary theory is
sometimes of little help, to put it cautiously, when we mean to make sense of
the complex realities of, say, gender identities as they are actually lived in
historical societies.
Essentially, I am suggesting that the human
species’ “psychological exile,” of which E. O. Wilson speaks (Consilience
224), is more drastic than sociobiologists and their followers in the
humanities are willing to recognize. Carroll and other philologists working in
this field have significantly contributed to our knowledge of human evolution
by describing the arts as “an adaptive response to the adaptive problem
produced by the adaptive capacities of high intelligence.” But the excessive
invocation of “adaptive” explanations in this sentence obscures the
epistemological demands of studying “high intelligence.” If we, as humanists,
are crucially concerned with “the social skills required by living in exceptionally
complex social environments” (as Carroll phrases it, my emphasis), and if the
complexity of these environments has something to do with the emergence of types
of sociability and meaning-making that can objectify themselves, thus
qualitatively transcending other natural orders and turning evolution into
history, we are probably well advised to take seriously social,
historiographical, and literary theories that have understood something about
the limits of biological perspectives and empirical methods for the study of
culture.
As Carroll says, common sense is a good
antidote to many of the scholastic excesses in contemporary literary theory.
But there is a point where common sense can turn into a resentful ideology. I
find this to be the case in the institutional posturing of much neo-naturalist
scholarship: there is a sense of camp mentality in these writings, a sense of
bringing about a backlash against the omnipresent evil of “constructivism,” a sense of being unfairly left behind and left
out in academia, a sense of being beleaguered by powerful enemies with
conspiratorial power interests. Such partisanship will do a disservice to anyone’s
research agenda—it will do so all the more if one makes exalted claims about
one’s own scientific neutrality.
Having been invited by Joseph Carroll to
compose this critique, I add with some hesitation that I find this camp
mentality particularly pronounced in the Anglo-American sphere, where
discussions of science and attendant scientific self-definitions have been
determined by the larger context of ongoing culture wars. It is probably no
coincidence that many American neo-naturalists take their cue from utopian
visionaries like E. O. Wilson or from gifted polemicists and popularizers like
Steven Pinker. Carroll’s essay, too, mainly refers to American sources, and
quotes Wilson’s agenda of “consilience” as if it was an
uncontroversial, almost self-evident program. I think it would have been
profitable to consider outside perspectives, including European variants of
neo-naturalist scholarship. Karl Eibl’s book Animal Poeta, with its
qualms about Wilsonian sociobiology, would have been an obvious candidate
(although Eibl disagrees with most of my points here).[43] In
any case, to bring in reflections from different cultures and languages is, once
more, a particularly appropriate strategy of studying culture, because it
facilitates awareness of the fact that even and especially the most
self-assured universals are shot through with historical and local knowledge.
In this regard, what is remarkable about Wilson and Pinker from a philological
(and perhaps a European) perspective is not that they are insensitive to fine
aesthetics, as we are sometimes told, but that their partisan ideal of
trans-disciplinarity and their hostility to cultural studies derives to a
considerable degree from their self-understanding as cultural warriors: from a
social and institutional rather than a purely scientific position.
In sum, there is of course nothing
inherently wrong with programs such as EvoS at SUNY Binghamton. And Carroll
does a good job outlining the promises of such and similar interdisciplinary
endeavors. But as long as neo-naturalist approaches refuse to engage genuinely
with contemporary theories of culture in the humanities, and instead prefer to
cast themselves in the cliquish, perhaps resentful role of iconoclastic
truth-sayers, their scholarly practices will continue to fall short of their
scientific ambitions. I wish they could become more equanimous about their
epistemological position and less assuming in their methodological self-image.
Not only would this improve their rhetoric; it would also benefit their
scholarship. Who knows, they might even begin to gain something from reading,
with sensitivity to cultural and disciplinary contexts, fellow theoreticians of
the human such as Foucault and Derrida.
The Bottlenecks of Literary Darwinism
In his book, Literary Darwinism,
Professor Carroll observes that “the professional advantages of
poststructuralist doctrine should be obvious. It enables literature professors
to adopt a prefabricated critical stance that depends in no way on the
empirical validity of their findings”(16). Couldn’t literary Darwinism afford
its practitioners similar “professional advantages”? With the corporatization
of the academy in full swing, empirical studies on literature, in their pursuit
of “practical” and/or “valid” claims, wish to make literary criticism into a
more “marketable” field. By transforming the literary arm of the humanities
into an increasingly scientific or factual realm, empiricism irrevocably
defeats one of literary studies’ greatest attributes: its ability to exist as
something other than scientific. In other words, if English majors want to
construct empirical studies, then perhaps they should major in Sociology, not
Literature.
Phillip Barrish, whose 1991 article on the
confluence between Darwinism and contemporary theory Carroll has called a
strained effort “to depict Darwin himself as a proto-deconstructive exemplar of
irrationalism and indeterminacy” (Literary Darwinism 27) remarks that
“deconstructive, psychoanalytic, and Marxist models can be linked by their
‘family resemblance’ to Darwin’s description of a category of random variation
that is accumulated in ‘certain definite directions’ to produce what appears as
a natural order. In addition, the ethical imperative of Darwin’s theory, which
entails that our conception of God be replaced by an acknowledgement of
variation and of the mechanism of natural selection, prepares for the ethical
dimensions of each of these contemporary theories” (441). Though many scholars
have combined deconstructive, psychoanalytic, and Marxist approaches, doing the
same with literary Darwinism appears to be undesirable by Carroll, though he
admits that “evolutionary literary study […] is one more ‘approach’ or ‘school’
that merits inclusion in casebooks and theoretical surveys” and that “a Darwinian
‘reading’ of this or that text” is certainly plausible. However, elsewhere he
argues that the “more ambitious adherents” to literary Darwinism aim at
“fundamentally altering the paradigm within which literary study is now
conducted.” The goal for “consilience” is certainly laudable. However, does
consilience, in Carroll’s view, simply stamp out the uniqueness of literary
study? Are we to assume that literature should merely be subsumed by the
sciences? Again, though the idea of a harmonious, balanced, and
interdisciplinary relationship between the sciences and humanities seems to
exist as an ideal, the universalization of all academic disciplines, as with
the universalization of humanity (a goal of colonialism and globalization),
could ultimately lead to homogeneity rather than innovation.
In his defense of humanism entitled Humanism
and Democratic Criticism, Edward Said criticizes “all the supposedly
neoconservative philosophy condemning whole classes and races to eternal
backwardness, proving—if that’s the right word—in the worst Darwinian sense that
some people deserve ignorance, poverty, ill health, and backwardness” (22;
emphasis added). Let’s counter this statement with Darwin’s own words. Writing
to William Graham in July 1881, he remarks, “I could show fight on natural
selection having done and doing more for the progress of civilization than you
seem inclined to admit. Remember what risk the nations of Europe ran, not so
many centuries ago of being overwhelmed by the Turks, and how ridiculous such
an idea now is! The more civilized so-called Caucasian races have beaten the
Turkish hollow in the struggle for existence. Looking to the world at no very
distant date, what an endless number of the lower races will have been
eliminated by the higher civilized races throughout the world” (F. Darwin 316).
Sadly, though “Darwin’s theory of the evolution of the species represented a
genuine advance for science” and has become the basis for scientific study into
the twenty first century, “it was used to bolster ideas of racial supremacy: in
his Descent of Man (1871), Darwin wrote: ‘Extinction follows chiefly
from the competition of tribe with tribe, and race with race. […] When
civilized nations come into contact with barbarians the struggle is short’” (qtd.
in Loomba 57). Who determines which nations are civilized and which are
barbarous?[44]
What happens when humans take the laws of natural selection into their own
hands? It is no surprise that a critic of postcolonialism and imperialism like
Said views Darwinism in a negative light. Colonialism aimed to make
“barbarians” more “civilized” by making them more “English,” “French,”
“German,” etc. The colonialist efforts to make “inferior” nations more
“acceptable” by transforming their citizens into imperfect subjects of this or
that empire is certainly not natural. Is the oppression of humans by other
humans part and parcel of human nature? Certainly, both evolutionary theory and
imperialism encompass many more complexities. However, is it even possible to
compose a Darwinist “reading” of a postcolonial and/or colonial text? How do
Darwin’s position as a white, imperialist male and the appropriation of his
ideas for colonial supremacy affect an analysis of a “classic” postcolonial
work like Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart or Buchi Emecheta’s The
Joys of Motherhood? We can also extend these questions to works in which
issues of feminism or homosexuality are extant. If “human females have evolved
a need to secure the bonded attachment of a male willing to invest resources in
them and their offspring,” then where is the space for sexualities that deviate
from this aspect of “human nature”? By depending on heterosexual procreation,
natural selection and its ancillary theories seemingly exclude individuals who
are “other” to the dominant norm. Judging from his extensive bibliography and
our own research, neither Carroll nor any of the other prominent literary
Darwinists have produced an effective Darwinist reading of a postcolonial or
feminist text. Can it be done? Here is where an intersection among
deconstruction, Marxism, postcolonialism, and Darwinism might be useful and,
indeed, quite interesting. In this way, implementing literary Darwinism into
the sphere of contemporary critical theory, combining it with one or many of
the other critical approaches to literature already circulating, could truly
add something ingenious to the discipline. To invoke the words of Gayatri
Spivak, whose own critical combinations of deconstruction, feminism, Marxism,
and subaltern studies have added much to the field over the past four decades:
I propose to overwrite the globe. Globalization is the imposition of
the same system of exchange everywhere. […] The planet is in the species of
alterity, belonging to another system; and yet we inhabit it, on loan. […] To
be human is to be intended toward the other. We provide for ourselves what we
think is the origin of this animating gift: mother, nation, god, nature. These
are names of alterity, some more radical than others. Planet-thought opens up
to embrace an inexhaustible taxonomy of such names, including but not identical
with the whole range of human universals: aboriginal animism as well as the
spectral white mythology of postrational science. If we imagine ourselves as
planetary subjects rather than global agents, planter creatures rather than
global entities, alterity remains underived from us; it is not our dialectical
negation, it contains us as much as it flings us away. (72-73)
Take note of Spivak’s language. She uses terms such as “species,”
“taxonomy,” “creatures,” and “human universals,” with each evoking discursive
elements of evolutionary science.[45]
Whereas globalization appears to unite cultures, nations, and individuals, it
does so through homogenization rather than alterity. Here, the shared “ethical
imperative” of Darwinism and contemporary critical thought about which Barrish
writes figures prominently. Rethinking humans as planetary subjects, as part of
a species, requires a giving of agency to all people.
And doesn’t this
aspect of literary Darwinism account for its greatest strengths and
possibilities as an interpretive paradigm? Why apologize—why mince words about
the efficacy of adaptationist literary analysis—when we can readily intuit that
well-founded literary characters must surely demonstrate distinctly human traits
in order to exist as round (as opposed to flat) characterological specimens?
Thanks to the groundbreaking work conducted by Carroll and others, we can point
to adaptationist criticism as one of the most viable interpretive tools
available in contemporary literary study. Indeed, adaptationist criticism
assists us in understanding the foundations of literary character by virtue of
its attention to the manner in which human beings respond to change, as well as
by how they attempt to survive and presumably flourish under their new
conditions. Adaptationist criticism recognizes the ceaseless conflict between
biological and environmental influences upon the nature of human development
and individuation. Carroll asserts that adaptationist criticism is
“fundamentally opposed to poststructuralist theories” and suggests a wholly
distinctive way of reading texts, one valuing the notion that “humans in all
ages and cultures display a common, basic set of motives, feelings, and ways of
thinking. [Adaptationist literary scholars] believe further that literature
commonly depicts human nature, that it is produced by human nature, and that it
satisfies the needs of human nature” (“Adaptationist Literary Study” 19).
Adaptationist criticism is already unique in its ability to bridge the sciences
and the humanities, fashioning a critical methodology that envelops biology and
textuality. As an analytical tool, adaptationist criticism swerves away from
the poststructuralist belief that literary characters are simply autonomous
textual creations and favors a reassessment of literary personages as
reflections of genuine human beings, who—consistently confronted with conflict
and choice—must make decisions that impact their capacity for survival.
Additionally, these human characters quite often contend with genetic
predispositions that disable their ability to make certain choices. Human
nature is most frequently responsible for the positions in which many humans
(and literary characters) find themselves; driven by their natural instincts,
human characters decide to subsist or expire, although their environments may
or may not facilitate their desired outcomes. “Literary representations are not
disconnected from the material world,” David P. Barash and Nanelle Barash
write. “Even the loftiest products of human imagination are, first, emanations
of that breathing, eating, sleeping, defecating, reproducing, evolving critter
known as Homo sapiens” (B8).
In Evolution and Literary Theory (1995),
Carroll ascertains three levels of interaction between literary criticism and
evolutionary psychology, including human nature, cultural order, and individual
identity. He argues that human nature involves a wide range of cultural
productions, and these “cultural forms are themselves the product of a complex
interaction among various innate dispositions and between innate dispositions
and variable environmental conditions” (150, 152). Given that much of Darwin’s
philosophy recognizes that in order for civilization to advance, human beings
must adapt, we can usefully understand the nature of effective character
construction in terms of the inextricable relationship that exists between
human beings and the ceaseless forces of evolution. With Carroll’s levels of
interaction, human nature functions as the determining factor in a given
character’s capacity for adapting or maladapting—for living well and
flourishing or, conversely, slipping into the oblivion of status quo. Carroll
defines human nature in terms of two essential propositions: firstly, that
“innate human dispositions exercise a powerful shaping force on all forms of
cultural order,” and secondly, that “all such forces operate in a tight web of
systemic interdependency such that the modification of any one element has a
distinct effect on all the other elements within the system” (153).
With its deft mergence of evolutionary thought and textual analysis,
literary Darwinism affords us with a keen understanding of the makeup of
literary characters—of their “innate human dispositions,” their human
nature—and the attendant agency, moreover, that they require as distinct human
representational forms. Interpretive structures like adaptationist criticism
provide us with an expansive means for assessing literary characters in terms
of all of their profundity and idiosyncrasies. Yet, by not engaging with
representative texts from other theoretical paradigms in order to foment debate
and forge alliances with them, literary Darwinism closes itself off from the truly
radical dialogue that might ensue. And this is a shame, given that literary
Darwinism remains one of the most liberating, progressive, and challenging of
analytic modes. One way or another, we owe a great debt to pioneering scholars
like Professor Carroll for leading the way.
Completing the Paradigm: In Pursuit of Evidence
Why do we need an evolutionary theory of literature?
Apart from its intrinsic interest and significance (of which more in a moment),
does it make literature more accessible? Does it enhance our experience of
reading (or hearing) it? Does it provide us with new knowledge about the human
characteristics that are at the core of literature? Does it tell us anything
about what may be distinctive to literary texts? Is the claim to scientific
rigour that it brings to the field a credible or useful one? Is it likely to
resolve the “crisis of morale in the humanities,” as Carroll puts it, following
several decades of poststructuralist hegemony?
In his target paper
Professor Carroll insists that evolutionary literary theory has the potential
to reorganize the whole field of literary scholarship. The more boldly and
comprehensively this claim is made, the more these and others questions press
themselves upon us for answers. In my comments I will consider how far
Carroll’s approach can answer these specific questions: they are the questions
that interest me, but I assume that literary scholars who don’t simply dismiss
evolutionary thinking out of hand would also wish to raise them.
Intrinsically, the
arguments for the significance of an evolutionary approach to literature seem
undeniable. That human beings have evolved and, along with our other
capacities, have developed facilities for producing and responding to
literature, suggests that we will understand ourselves and literature better by
considering what those facilities might be. If Carroll is right, such inquiry
should help create new perspectives on our cognitive and emotional capacities,
on formal aspects of texts, and on their social and historical functioning. So
what has been achieved so far? In his paper Carroll lays out the agenda for the
evolutionary paradigm, as he sees it, with theoretical clarity and in some
detail, but he includes little by way of example showing what evolutionary
literary criticism can accomplish. What might we expect? Here are some comments
drawn from Carroll’s paper.
Literature is
important for “organizing motivational systems disconnected from the immediate
promptings of instinct.” Carroll has in mind here the value of narrative in
enabling us to imagine and rehearse situations offline, thus human beings with
such a capacity are more adaptive and resilient. Similarly, he mentions
Pinker’s notion that “literary plots provide game plan models.” The power of
such models comes in part from the emotions they evoke. The arts, Carroll says,
“fashion an imaginative universe in which the forces at work in the environment
and inside the mind are brought into emotionally meaningful relations to one
another.” How do such claims illuminate an evolutionary reading of a literary
text? Take Brian Boyd’s account of Mansfield
Park.
In Boyd’s evolutionary
view “literature arises out of deep-rooted human needs and
capacities,” not from the codes of structuralism or the ideologies of
historicism (Boyd, “Jane” 13). Thus the central concern of Austen’s novel is
with mating strategies. In particular it “focuses overwhelmingly on female
choice,” where “females choose males as partners on the basis of their ability
to support the offspring” (16). This helps account for Maria’s impulse to marry
the first eligible suitor she sees, Mr. Rushworth; it suggests why, against
powerful family pressures, Fanny Price firmly declines to marry the
philandering Henry Crawford – she has detected him to be a cheat; and it
explains the sense of rightness at the end with her marriage to Edmund. This
reading reminds us that despite a highly patriarchal culture, the apparently
weakest character, Fanny Price, turns out to be the most successful. As Boyd
notes, much about the novel “can be interpreted in terms of biologically
evolved characteristics of human life, rather than as no more than the product
of a particular cultural moment” (23). In this perspective, the novel teaches
us how to read its “game plan model” through the universalizing power of its
cultural specificity. “No action or event is, for humans, ever just
itself,” as Carroll puts it (28). Thus we have to puzzle out why the evasion of
the locked gate in Rushworth’s garden by Henry and Maria seems such a
transgression; or why, later, Fanny resolutely resists taking part in the
theatricals. At such moments an evolutionary reading like Boyd’s helps us to
see particularly clearly the nexus of emotion and environment – what is at
stake for Fanny and the characters around her – and why Fanny’s judgements at
such predicaments are so exigent (and always right!).
As Boyd acknowledges,
however, his reading of Mansfield
Park says little about Austen’s “artistic powers and problems” (23)
– her tone, her language, her characterization, and other features of the text.
His approach reads the text, albeit eloquently and tactfully, and with
appropriate regard for its historical specificity, as a case study of human
mating strategies (female in particular). Put in this light, we can see that Pride and Prejudice affords a
similar reading – a successful mating strategy in which the heroine pulls off a
marriage with a higher status suitor. Indeed, this is the theme of a number of
other novels, including a slew of modern romance fictions with little literary
pretension. If the value of fiction for us, then, could be explained only in
terms of its disconnected “motivational systems” and its “game plan models,”
this would surely fall short of accounting for what is specifically literary in
a text such as Austen’s. Is this as far as an evolutionary approach can go?
What is literary? How
should we define “art” in order to bring it within the scope of an evolutionary
approach? Here Carroll might benefit from an important point made by Ellen
Dissanayake (“Making” 28-9): that to account for the evolution of art we should
consider the art practised communally over the last 30,000 years or more, not
just the fine or rare art that we tend to associate with the term now. What
qualities made it adaptive? In the light of Carroll’s criteria, what “adaptive
problem” did it resolve in the ancestral environment (26)?
Without going back to
the tribal environment, which I am not qualified to examine (but see
Dissanayake, Homo), here
are two clues. First, consider Jonathan Rose’s findings on working class
readers from the nineteenth century. Through surviving memoirs and letters,
Rose found that a number of impoverished readers with only the most basic elementary
education, and with no literary education or prior familiarity with literature,
were able to pick up literary texts by authors ranging from Homer, through
Dickens, to Hardy, and to read them immediately and with understanding and
pleasure. These were not readers who had acquired the conventions of literary
reading, supposed to be essential by theorists such as Culler or Rabinowitz. In
addition, these were readers who, when in a position to choose, preferred to
read what we now regard as canonical texts rather than texts written and
published in penny editions specifically for working class readers. What was
the source of their interest? Rose points to the engagement with character and
what we have called the “game plan models,” whereby readers learned about a
different world and, in some cases, how to become a part of it. A reading of
their comments also shows that some readers were enthralled by the language of
the literary texts they read, by its sounds and texture, by the novelty of
unfamiliar words. This suggests a second clue.
In our empirical work
(Miall and Kuiken) on readers’ responses to foregrounding (striking stylistic
features in texts) we have found that all readers tend to be sensitive to it,
at least to its presence in the modernist short stories we asked them to read.
This was shown in several ways: by longer reading times for sentences rich in
foregrounding, by higher ratings on a strikingness scale for such sentences,
and by higher ratings for feeling. We and others have replicated this effect
whether working with readers with an advanced literary education, or with
readers with little interest in or experience of literary reading.
What appears to be at
issue here is what he have called defamiliarization, following the theoretical
work of the Russian Formalist critics such as Shklovsky and the British
Romantic writers such as Coleridge and Shelley. In the evolutionary framework,
however, we can situate this in a wider context: elsewhere (Miall 190) I have
classed the response to foregrounding as one type of dehabituation. Given the
complexity of our responses to the natural and social environment and the
rapidity with which our (mature) cognitive system identifies and evaluates the
world around us, here is the value of a system that, within a prescribed space,
calls our existing schemas into question: literary art offers us new
perceptions, unfamiliar feelings, fresh evaluations. Through literary
experience dehabituation provides a flexibility in feeling and thinking that is
almost certainly adaptive. It is a solution to the problem of stereotyped,
stock responses to the world which, in everyday terms, enable us to perform so
efficiently. As Patrick Hogan has shown (“Literary Universals”), foregrounding,
being found in the literature of every culture, can be considered a universal,
a defining feature of literariness, and is thus a strong candidate for being
analysed in evolutionary terms.
This leads to two
further considerations. First, although in his target paper Carroll has placed
a good deal of emphasis on contributing fields, arguing for the benefits of
“scientific method,” such as “a rigorous empirical analysis of cognitive
mechanisms,” the importation of theories and approaches from outside the field
of literature itself brings the risk that the distinctively literary qualities
of literature will be misrepresented or overlooked – a danger that “Humanistic
sensitivity to the fine shades of tone and style” will likely not be effective
enough to avert. As with dehabituation, with theoretical roots going back to
Coleridge, literary theories that arise within and are inherent to the literary
domain must be regarded just as seriously as those from the social sciences. If
there is a distinctive quality to literature, here is where we might expect to
find some of its elements. An evolutionary role for literature, we might
hypothesize, only developed as it did for this reason, that human beings turned
to literature for experiences unavailable elsewhere. Thus literary theories,
drawn from the literary domain (regarding such matters as style, narrative
structure, genre), must be regarded as central to the evolutionary endeavour,
if they can illuminate what is inherent to literary experience from the
Pleistocene up to Jane Austen and beyond.
Second, remembering
that most of the history of art occurred before the development of the high art
with which we are now (in the West, at least) most familiar, we should work
with ordinary readers as far as possible to help validate our proposals. Like
the readers in Rose’s study, these will be readers who turn to literature
primarily for the experience it has to offer – for compelling narratives, for
the pleasures of literary style – not, as we see practiced in literature
departments, reading for the sake of interpreting a text – pursuing the Rule of
Abstract Displacement, as Rabinowitz (139) has put it. Systematic empirical
study of real readers, with effective experimental controls where appropriate,
will do more than any other innovation we can envisage to bring together “the
humanities and the evolutionary social sciences,” the consummation that Carroll
wishes for. This approach, to return to my opening questions, should in the
long run elicit or confirm the values that are central to the literary experience:
thus, literature will become more accessible (with education making fewer
inappropriate demands). Knowing better why we read may enhance our future
literary experiences; and this, in turn, will teach us to know ourselves better
Response to Joseph Carroll’s “An Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Study”
SUNY Binghamton
As a member of the interdisciplinary
program mentioned by Carroll in closing (Binghamton University’s Evolutionary
Studies Program (EvoS)), I have no reservations with the claim that
evolutionary theory as it pertains to human psychology and culture has strong
predictive and synthesizing powers that can be of value to literary scholars.
Evolutionary theory does provide a powerful, integrated framework for
predicting what will be of short- and long-term interest to human beings.
Moreover, it is a valuable theoretical tool, as Carroll suggests, not only
because it can tell us something about regularities in humans’ cognitive,
perceptual, and affective systems (which are engaged during the reading
process) but also because it provides a life-history framework. Life history
theory predicts at a very basic level of organization that at different points
in an individual’s species-typical development, different motivations and goals
will, on average, predominate. Imaginative representations of people, places,
and situations surrounding such motivations and goals unquestionably recur in
popular literary genres. The most notable examples are the romance novel,
adventure and survival stories, and the bulk of world folklore. Clearly,
though, conflicts surrounding life-history motivations and goals are present to
some degree in virtually all literature by nature of their inevitability in
life. No theories other than those stemming from evolutionary theory can
presently explain such regularities in content across literary traditions. As
such, there is no question, in my mind, that evolutionary theory deserves
literary scholars’ greater attention if only for the larger picture it can
provide of how regularities in the human life cycle reflect basic, recurrent
concerns in literature.
Importantly, however, finding
biologically-based regularities in content or theme is not the limit of
evolutionary literary theory as developed by Carroll. The model presented in
Carroll’s article is fundamentally an interactionist model that can assist in
understanding the production and reception of literary meaning in specific
cultural contexts. In this model, authors’ or readers’ literary meaning can be
analyzed and interpreted as the product of how their species typical
characteristics are shaped by unique cultural values, and further colored by
the vicissitudes of individual identities. Style and form, to put it simply,
are the aesthetic delivery mechanisms for such meaning. And, as noted by
Carroll, humans’ shared perceptual and cognitive predispositions provide useful
starting points for theorizing about how human’s unique mental style so
effortlessly constructs narratives with considerable cross-cultural regularities.
Thus, there is evident effort in Carroll’s paradigm to examine how literature
comes into being, how humans derive meaning from it, and how such meaning is
dependent on cognitive and cultural constraints.
Critics of the evolutionary paradigm, however,
have often ignored the breadth of Carroll’s evolutionary framework. Despite the considerable space dedicated to
Carroll’s formulation that all realist and symbolic figuration necessarily
involves human universals, cultural particularities, and the colorings of
individual identity, his project, and those who have followed him, has been
critically reduced to a naïve search and find exercise involving biologically
based human universals. Evolutionists
have been accused of being “biological through and through” (Benzon) “ignoring
the cultural and technological extensions of human knowledge” (Richardson 12)
and in danger of becoming “nothing more than a latter-day Freudianism,
performing its ritual unveilings of psychic secrets in hunter-gatherer dress”
(Easterlin, “Hans” 256).
These criticisms do represent legitimate
concerns. At least two such simplistic readings have been published (see
Perchan and Barash and Barash). One of these was used recently, and rather
selectively I might add, to criticize the adequacy of an evolutionary approach
for attending to the complexity of literary expression and reception
(Goodheart). While I don’t share such criticisms, evolutionists should be more
openly critical of any simplistic effort to reduce literary meaning to behavioral
universals rather than openly accept them as kindred efforts in an upstart
field.
Nevertheless, by and large, accusations
that the limit of the evolutionary approach is biological theme-finding do not
obtain at the theoretical or interpretive level of most work done by those who
associate themselves with Carroll’s paradigm. The interactionist model for
understanding literary meaning has been employed fruitfully in many published
interpretations for some time now. Interpretations of specific literary works
by Brian Boyd, Judith Saunders, Ian Jobling, Marcus Nordlund, and Brett Cooke,
among others, are never mentioned by those who brand the field “biological
through and through” for the simple reason that such interpretations amount to
inconvenient counterevidence for those who seem bent on diminishing the
theoretical importance of representations of behavior in literary analysis.
This being said, even if one appreciates
the interactionist core of the evolutionary paradigm, I think Carroll is still open
to criticism, to some degree, for the primacy he places on life-history
universals. Specifically, this regards his claim that “the governing
terms in an evolutionary critique are not metaphysical abstractions, mid-level
social and psychological concepts, or formalist principles. The governing terms
are the urgent needs and driving forces in life—survival, reproduction,
kinship, social affiliation, dominance, aggression, and the needs of the
imagination…the rhythms of the life cycle shape the analytic categories through
which Darwinians make sense of literary depictions.” This may seem
contradictory to some: an interactionist model that grants primacy to
biological regularities.
I agree with this primacy to some degree
because I do not see a reason for exempting human preferences and motivations,
on average, from the logic of inclusive fitness. While the frequency of such
universals in world literature remains to be studied in any significant depth,
most stories do seem centered around some issue pertaining to humans’ species
typical life-history cycle. Jonathan Gottschall’s work on world folklore and
Patrick Colm Hogan’s work on literary universals speaks to the fruitfulness of
starting with such regularities. As a preliminary starting point for literary
analysis, a focus on evolutionary content seems sound if only for the frequency
of such representations and for the emotional receptivity most people have for
such topics.
This
being said, I think that the prospects of getting more people on board with the
evolutionary paradigm will require more significant empirical demonstrations
that the presence of “the driving forces of life” in literary texts affects
real world thought and behavior in predictable and significant ways. This will
prove difficult. It is one thing—and no small thing, granted—to create an
interpretive model based upon evolutionary theory that grounds analysis within
life history categories and supplements it with attention to style, form and
the pertinent cognitive mechanisms involved. It is quite another challenge to
demonstrate that readers attend to and incorporate most saliently in their mind
the evolutionarily relevant behavior that is represented in texts. It may be
the case that stories, as Carroll suggests, function in some way to organize
and fine-tune the cognitive-behavioral predispositions of individual minds.
However, empirically, we have a long way to go before we can isolate the impact
of specific behavioral representations from specific stories on the specific
behaviors of readers.
Empirically establishing the primacy of
“the driving forces of life” is central, I think, to the success of the
evolutionary paradigm because a critic can ask: don’t all textual elements that impinge upon meaning stimulate
and engage readers’ minds in an inextricable simultaneity? How do we pull apart
the relative contributions of form, style, and content? And, if we place
primacy on “the driving forces of life,” does it necessarily follow that the
claimed “cognitive” aspects of literary experience such as levels of recursion
in Theory of Mind, or the aptness and sophistication of metaphors and
conceptual blends, play a secondary, and largely, attention-getting role in
literary narratives? It very well could be the case that readers are not reading
for metaphor or complex
demonstrations of Theory of Mind as much as through them to get to emotionally evocative content
that they internalize and perhaps later use in their everyday lives. But again,
if it cannot be demonstrated empirically that “the driving forces of
life” deserve the primacy that Carroll’s evolutionary paradigm grants them,
then I fear that debates between evolutionists, cognitivists, and other
scientifically oriented branches of literary study are likely to become mired
in theoretical arguments of emphasis—not evidence—concerning what individual
scholars and disciplinary sub-groups deem most important to the reading and
interpretive process. Such arguments of emphasis are already evident in
exchanges between evolutionary and cognitive literary scholars. Whereas Carroll
seeks to subsume cognitive literary study within evolutionary literary study,
Ellen Spolsky recently suggested that evolutionists “must build upon” (815)
work done in cognitive literary theory in order for such work to be meaningful.
Both evolutionists and cognitivists clearly feel that what they study is of
vital importance to explaining the power of and our capacities for literary
experience. The most precious future work will be that which can help
adjudicate between the competing primacies that certain groups will want to
place on their topics of study.
To produce quantitatively replicable,
empirical knowledge within the field of literary studies is already being
accomplished by some evolutionarily minded literary scholars (Carroll, Graphing;
Gottschall, Literature; Miall, Literary). This is a fantastic
achievement and deserves the highest praise. As more studies are done, we can
begin to assess to what extent diverse samples of readers understand and
perhaps privilege evolutionarily salient content in relation to other cultural,
formal, and cognitive aspects of the reading process, and how this all affects
their real-world thought and behavior.
Evolutionists might claim that what I am
asking to be demonstrated empirically is accepted commonsense within
evolutionary circles. The critics of the evolutionary paradigm and those who
advocate the importance of some other facet of the reading process are not
likely to concede the point easily. Questions about governing principles are
empirical questions after all and they needn’t linger for years to come as
irreconcilable points of emphasis, which is what I fear they are turning into.
The empirical arm of the evolutionary paradigm is especially important but so
too is outlining a clear direction for future empirical research, one which
will serve to put such central theoretical questions to the test.
Reflections on Literary Darwinism
Catherine Salmon
Psychology Department
University of Redlands
Catherine_salmon@redlands.edu
Joseph Carroll has
done an excellent job outlining some of the accomplishments of this fresh
approach to literature. Unsurprisingly, I approve of the endeavor, being a PhD
in evolutionary psychology who started out majoring in biology with a minor in
comparative literature. Back in the day, I loved those literature classes. Or
at least, I loved the reading of Homer and Virgil, and later on the works of
Shakespeare, Dostoyevsty, and Baudelaire. But I never
quite understood the point of the types of analyses that the professors wanted.
It wasn’t that they were difficult to do (and the psychoanalytic ones were
certainly fun) but I saw them as an intellectual exercise, not as something
that provided enlightenment as to the “true” motives behind the characters or author(s)
or the enduring appeal of certain plots or character types. In other words, I
didn’t “buy” them, and so I lost interest. Years later, during the last year or
so of my PhD program, I developed an interest in studying erotic fiction and
films from an evolutionary perspective with a particular focus on how
differences in the sexual psychologies of men and women have shaped the market
for erotica (romance and other erotic literature for women and largely
pornography for men). I also began to read articles by Carroll, Brett Cooke,
and Jon Gottschall which rekindled my interest in the study of literature.
While in my own work I have largely viewed it as a source of data on human
nature, the new Literary Darwinians have shown me the possibility of a study of
literature that is not simply an intellectual exercise but something integrated
with modern scientific psychology and anthropology.
In An
Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Study, Carroll raises the issue of
whether the arts are an adaptation in and of themselves. Clearly, involvement
in the arts, defined broadly, is a human universal. However, the human desire
to produce and consume fiction could have two possible explanations which he
outlines. One is that our involvement in fiction is simply the byproduct of
psychological adaptations that were designed by natural selection to serve
other functions. We are not designed to engage in fictional experiences, we are
susceptible to them. Pinker has been one of the leading proponents of this
perspective, which is sometimes explained with the image of the arts as
something that “picks the locks” of our brains’ pleasure circuits.[46]
The other
explanation, first articulated by Tooby and Cosmides (“Does Beauty Build?”), is
that our involvement in fictional experiences is an adaptation, something we
are designed to do because of its’ fitness benefits.
With fiction unleashing our reactions to
potential lives and realities, we feel more richly and adaptively about what we
have not actually experienced. This allows us not only to understand others’
choices and inner lives better, but to feel our way more foresightfully to
adaptively better choices ourselves. (23)
As Carroll noted, I believe both explanations
may be correct and that different types of fiction may be successful because
they tap into either the lock-picking pleasure circuits or engage organizing
adaptations (Salmon and Symons, “Slash Fiction”). It may be that some of the
most successful tap into both.
When
raising the issue of empirical methodology, Carroll suggests that some literary
scholars would argue that while science focuses on patterns in the physical
world, the humanities focus on the qualitatively unique. Despite such claims,
“Trying to isolate literary study from psychological and historical generalizations
is a sophistical maneuver that will not stand against the simplest appeal to
factual evidence…literary critics cannot do without appeal to the regularities
of human psychology.” Without such regularities, specific works would not have
widespread appeal. The importing of methodology from the social sciences is one
way to collect such empirical data and will, I expect, continue to be a
fruitful endeavor for many in the field.
Related
to the issue of methodology is the suggestion that cognitive neuroscience may
have something to contribute to the question of the adaptive nature of the
arts. If the arts have an adaptive function, participation in them should “be
motivated as emotionally driven needs.” As such, they should be related to
specific forms of neurological activity which could theoretically be
identified. While I think this could be an interesting approach, I think the
current state of cognitive neuroscience makes it very easy to see how parts of
the brain light up when we ask people to do things/read/imagine/etc, what that
activity really means, or its implications, are much harder to determine with
any confidence. I might be more inclined to delve into the experiments of
motivation researchers and see if insights might be found there to illuminate
the question of the adaptive function of the arts.
“Can
the Darwinists produce formulations that are not only new but true?” (in the
target article). This is the important question. In my undergraduate years I
didn’t feel that much of literary analysis had anything to do with truth. But a
literary studies that examines the biological forces that dominate (or are
suppressed in) different works is a comparative literature that would be a
pleasure to experience, one consistent with our expanding knowledge of human
nature and the forces that shape us, knowledge collected from a wide variety of
evolutionary social sciences. One example is Robin Fox’s analysis of male
bonding in the epics, focusing on the importance of bonds between males in
terms of hunting and warfare (“Male Bonding”). He also notes more modern
examples such as Patrick O’Brian’s Master and Commander series of
novels, which also produced a motion picture with the same title. Many
action-adventure movies are often analyzed in terms of violence, such as so
called Asian “Gun-fu” films, ignoring the underlying themes of loyalty and
betrayal among men that permeate them.
I
would also suggest that the research Don Symons and I conducted on slash
stories (romantic/erotic narrative, written almost exclusively by women and for
women, in which both protagonists are expropriated male media characters, the
stars of various cop, spy, and science fiction televisions shows and movies as
well as literary works, think Sherlock Holmes and Dr. Watson, or Kirk and Spock
from Star Trek) and their readers (Salmon and Symons, “Slash Fiction” and Warrior
Lovers) demonstrates the new perspective that evolutionary minded thinking
brings to a study of literature, reinforcing Carroll’s argument that the
Darwinist framework is useful to literary studies. Most studies of this genre
have focused on women’s dissatisfaction with their own lives/bodies/men/etc,
ignoring the fact that these are basically a variant of the traditional romance
novel. The setting may be different, and the couple may both be male, but the
heart of the stories is still the trials and tribulations of finding and
keeping one’s true love. And their heart is this way because their authors and
readers are women and this particular adaptive problem is one that has been
faced by women over our evolutionary history. It is not as interesting to men
(and the reason why they aren’t voracious consumers of romances or chick
flicks) because their adaptive problems in the mating arena have been a bit
different. But from an evolutionary perspective slash fiction is not a surprise
or freakishly odd, just a variation on the appeal of romance to women. For this
sort of reason, I look forward to many future years of literary Darwinism.
Ideas of Order: Artists Describing the Arts
Judith P. Saunders
Marist College
Discussing the
adaptive functions of human art, Joseph Carroll highlights its role in
organizing the capacity of the mind to envision circumstances beyond the
immediate. Able to conceptualize future problems and pleasures, to anticipate a
multiplicity of outcomes for any event, to speculate about individual motives
or group dynamics, and even to foresee their own mortality, humans occupy a
mental universe far larger than their actual physical and social environment.
“The Brain—is wider than the sky—,” as Emily Dickinson observes (Poem 262). The
uniquely anticipatory, creatively constructive characteristics of human
psychology have proven to be a source of strength for the species, ensuring
“behavioral flexibility” in handling “contingent circumstances” (in target
article). At the same time, however, these abilities are the source of
“potential chaos” and “psychological exile” for the restlessly hypothesizing
individual mind (Wilson 224-25). By ordering and interpreting the welter of
interior hopes, fears, and schemes, art counters psychic chaos and isolation:
deliberately shaped artifacts—in paint, in music, in words—seek to teach, to
console, to cheer, or to inspire.
The ordered completeness of the imagined
worlds artists construct is underscored by their recognition of the fragmented,
confusing character of human consciousness. Without assistance such as that
supplied by art, individuals tend to become lost in the dismaying multiplicity
of their own projections, memories, and hypotheses. The sometimes overpowering
richness of the external environment is magnified, on a moment-by-moment basis,
by an avalanche of interior responses to it. In consequence, as Wallace Stevens
points out, “we live in a constellation / Of patches and of pitches, / Not in a
single world” (“July Mountain”). No one has described the “thousand odd,
disconnected fragments” comprising individual awareness better than Virginia
Woolf: “hanging and bobbing and dipping and flaunting,” the contents of the
“rag-bag of odds and ends within us” tease and exasperate (Orlando 78).
Seeking to understand the self as “nothing but one self,” its life’s experience
as “a single, downright, bluff piece of work,” the individual is confronted
instead with a hodge-podge of interiority that recklessly overlays sense
impressions with the “capricious” effects of memory, apprehension, and desire
(310, 78). The result, Woolf avers, is that “nothing [can] ever be seen whole”:
“body and mind [are] like scraps of torn paper tumbling from a sack” (307).
This “chopping up small of body and mind” threatens to annihilate identity: one
feels “disassembled” by a myriad of “separate scraps” all simultaneously
attempting to define the self and direct its thinking (307). Woolf goes so far
as to speculate that consciousness is an amalgam of “many different people . .
. all having lodgement . . . in the human spirit,” each manifesting its own
eccentric “sympathies, little constitutions and rights” (308). Prufrock, T.S.
Eliot’s famous antihero, poignantly illustrates the psychologically
debilitating problem of the “proliferation of possibilities” Woolf so vividly
evokes (in target article): he finds himself immobilized by his capacity to
project negative outcomes. The frenzied activity of his mental operations (“a
hundred indecisions . . . a hundred visions and revisions” which “a minute will
reverse”) stands in ironic contrast to his social paralysis: “And how should I
presume?” (“The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock”).
Artists seek to counteract the chaos
within, Carroll points out, by fashioning “an imaginative universe,” an
alternative “virtual world” in which the plethora of possibilities generated by
the mind assumes a satisfyingly cohesive, coherent, and aesthetic form.
Literary artists have sought repeatedly to articulate this crucial feature of
their work: the creation of a compelling parallel universe. They have employed
powerful metaphors to describe the fictive realities into which they propel
their readers. John Keats invests linguistic structures with spatial,
political, and economic dimensions, for instance, when he likens the act of
reading great literature to travel through “realms of gold” (“On First Looking
into Chapman’s Homer”). Containing “states and kingdoms,” the virtual territory
of books assumes materiality, further exalted by attributes of sovereignty and
wealth. Artists themselves, it appears, are consciously aware that they are
creating alternative environments in which hypotheses may be tested, pleasures
tasted, plans revised, outcomes revisited, and dreams realized. Self-definition
is a pervasive impulse in literature; its creators offer frequent and eloquent
reminders of its unique benefits. Indeed, they frame explanations of their
purposes that offer undeniable support for evolutionarily-based theories of
art.
Artists stress the completeness, the
unarguable self-sufficiency, of a successfully devised virtual world; its
emotional and intellectual equivalency to any extra-textual reality depends in
large part upon its ability to “Comprehend the Whole—“ (Dickinson, Poem #236).
In a notable example, Wallace Stevens identifies a book of poems as “the planet
on the table,” granting astronomical vastness and autonomy to the literary
artifact (“The Planet on the Table”). His bold metaphor causes a volume of
verse that fits in a reader’s hands to grow enormously in stature as well as in
size: it becomes a recognizable, distinct entity in an overarching cosmic
system. William Shakespeare similarly praises the “shaping fantasies”
responsible for art in A Midsummer Night’s Dream (Harcourt edition, V.1:
5). Distinguishing the imaginative powers of the “poet” from those of “lover”
and “lunatic,” he points out that the latter two are victims of their own
imaginative constructs: the lover projects self-deceiving pictures of the
beloved (“sees Helen’s beauty in a brow of Egypt”), while the lunatic is
terrorized by images that derive from internal, rather than external, sources
of apprehension (“how easy is a bush supposed a bear”) (V.1: 11, 22). The poet,
in contrast, takes charge of imaginative processes to build a “strange and
admirable” new world (V.1:27). He converts mental images into “shapes, and
gives to airy nothing / A local habitation and a name” (V.1:16-17). Wielding
seemingly magical, transformative powers, the artist lends detail and substance
to the non-material universe of mind. The resulting artifact is far more
compelling and valuable than “fancy’s images” (such as those misleading the
lover or lunatic) because of the completeness of its aesthetic design (V.1:
25). The poet has invented a plausible, named habitation, an alternative
living space. All its parts fit together, moreover, ensuring internal
consistency, or “constancy”(V.1: 26).
The twentieth-century poet Charles
Tomlinson echoes Shakespeare’s insight that art inexplicably creates spaces
with “local” substance from the “airy nothing” of imaginative operations: “as
if a whole landscape night be unrolled / out of the atmosphere” (“Second
Song”). The mystery and paradox characterizing the seemingly habitable yet
ultimately unreal places art builds are recurrent topics in literature. Writers
invite readers into “a place always out of reach,” familiar yet alien
(Tomlinson “The Stair”). Yeats’s “holy city” of Byzantium is special because it
contains familiar elements but remains “out of nature” (“Sailing to
Byzantium”). There the “golden bough” retains its tree-like form but is
composed of inorganic materials; no matter how lifelike, it is the produce of
“artifice.” In the ekphrastic poem “On a Collage of Marie José Paz,” Tomlinson
explores this theme from the point of view of the visual arts. Noting that Paz
has composed her picture from “patches,” he finds himself fascinated by one
particular “scrap” in the design, one that serves two functions simultaneously.
This portion of the collage is not a plain, opaque scrap of paper; rather, it
is “a landscape photograph.” Even as it completes the surface design of a tree
trunk, therefore, it appears to open a “window” into another place entirely.
The artist has enlarged, indeed, doubled, the evocative power of her picture,
“clear[ing] a space / out of elements / neither here nor there.” The viewer is
invited irresistibly into the tree and tumbles like Alice down a rabbit-hole entry
into an exotic space: “this interior / turned inside out.”
Here Tomlinson provides a wonderful
formulation of the surprises readers encounter in the Oz of art. They enter
eccentrically crafted worlds in which physical, psychological, and social laws operate
inside out, that is, in a fashion both like and unlike their operations
in real time and space. The literary work provides an “outlook that would be
right,” as Stevens expresses it, enabling readers to feel “complete in an
unexplained completion” (“The Poem That Took the Place of a Mountain”). The
simultaneous resemblance and difference juxtaposing imaginative space to real
space fosters psychological distance, insight, and control: it is the source of
the solace and understanding art so often yields. (The small-mindedness of
eighteenth-century European politics reveals itself with splendid clarity,
consequently, in the miniaturized empire of Lilliput.) Climbing, here, into the
“scrap” that forms an entire “landscape” in Paz’s collage, Tomlinson’s poet-speaker
discovers that he is “free / in this tiny confine” (12-13). Art confronts us
with a “tiny” but complete version of ordinary reality, reducing its hugeness
and complexity to manageable proportions. In this deliberately limited space,
we are temporarily “free.” Like a topographical map, the story, poem, or play
enables its audience to comprehend a larger whole to which its details
correspond; in art, necessarily, the mapped country is always imaginary.
Metaphors stressing the miniaturizing
effect of art recur frequently as way of describing the sense of power readers
gain in the carefully delineated environment of literary space. Another example
by a contemporary writer is Mary Jo Salter’s “Cutlery,” a poem in which she
attempts to describe the appeal of a lapel pin decorated with diminutive
replicas of knife, fork, and spoon. These tiny implements delight the beholder
“because they aren’t real” and, at the same time, “because they are.” They
correspond to “life-sized” cutlery in every detail, but are too tiny to be of
any practical use. “In the doll’s house of art,” Salter concludes, “the table
is always set and a meal / deliciously out of question.” Art presents us with
phenomena, sensations, emotions, and conflicts like those in our “life-sized” world
but in a precisely bounded, risk-free environment. In this “doll’s house”
world, we enjoy the illusion of being in control, in charge, far-seeing, even
wise. The knowledge that this alternative world is as unreal as it is realistic
(the meals it sets forth never to be enjoyed) lends a bittersweet but
ultimately liberating flavor to our enjoyment.
“Deliciously,” art holds out for our
inspection imaginary territories that promise to be superior to the burdensome
complexities of the environments we actually inhabit: art ferries us to realms
of gold. “Heard melodies are sweet, but those unheard / Are sweeter,”
Keats assures his readers (“Ode on a Grecian Urn”). Art pipes “to the spirit”
rather than to the merely “sensual ear,” therefore; having “no tone,” the
“ditties” so composed remain gloriously “Exterior—to Time--” (Dickinson, Poem
176). With “small reason,” Stevens muses, we persist in thinking that “the
world imagined is the ultimate good” (Final Soliloquy of the Interior
Paramour”). Nothing on the street where we live, certainly, can compete with a
“pleasure dome” in Xanadu, that “savage” yet “enchanted” place of Coleridge’s
imaginings (“Kubla Khan”). Marked by diametric oppositions (“a sunny
pleasure-dome with caves of ice!”), Xanadu is unmistakably a realm of artifice,
and for that very reason seductive and precious.
Persistently writers locate the value of
literature in the escape it provides from oppressive forces in the reader’s
immediate environment. The young David Copperfield, for example, ameliorates
his wretchedness and that of his fellow pupils at a cruelly managed boarding
school with narrations based on books by his “favorite authors” (88). His
bedtime performances are dubbed a “‘regular Arabian Nights,’” an allusion
offering further evidence that the alternative realities a storyteller provides
can serve as a refuge from intolerable circumstances (88). Woolf makes the same
point in Orlando from an ironic perspective when she declares that
reading will “substitute a phantom for reality” (74). “Orlando . . . had only
to open a book for the whole vast accumulation [of his property] to turn to
mist”: it all “vanish[es],” “disappear[s],” “evaporate[s]” as the protagonist
loses himself in the temporarily more desirable space of artistic invention (74).
Although Orlando is using books to escape what appears to be an enviable
life—prosperous and aristocratic, replete with opportunity—he is no different
from young David Copperfield in his tendency to use literature as magic carpet:
it carries him, wonderfully, to a different place. “There is no Frigate like a
Book /To take us Lands away,” Dickinson tells us; it is a “chariot” that “bears
the Human soul” (Poem 466). In another poem Dickinson explains, very like an
Adaptationist, that the pleasure of literature lies in its capacity to engage
anticipatory or speculative mechanisms in the human psyche: books “cheer . . .
guests / With Banquettings to be—“; they “Enamor—in Prospective--” (Poem 249).
In fact, the visions designed by literary
artists prove so alluring, so all-absorbing, that writers sometimes point to
the perils inherent in their potency. The imaginary world of chivalry,
preserved and disseminated in books, provides the motivating impulse behind Don
Quixote’s mad questing. Forged in the world of mind, Don Quixote’s ideals are
as admirable as they are ridiculous, as inspiring in theory as they prove
destructive in practice. In the character of his eccentric protagonist,
Cervantes highlights the dangers of committing oneself with excessive zeal to a
single fictional reality. As Carroll indicates, “we do not have the option of
living outside our own imaginative constructs.” For members of the human
species, “life consists / Of propositions about life” (Stevens, “Men Made Out
of Words”). Typically, however, we are “constantly forming and reforming” the
imaginative structures that shape meaning for us. Don Quixote has become stuck
in a single mental construct; he is resistant to influences that might modify
or correct the vision of life transmitted by the one imagined world he has
determined to prefer.
Stephen Crane illustrates the same problem
in “A youth in apparel that glittered” (Poem 27). In this tiny narrative, a
young man dazzled by tropes from tales of chivalric valor puts on the costume
of knighthood and strolls into a “grim forest.” Assaulted there by a
dagger-wielding “assassin / attired all in garb of old days,” the youth
welcomes a death that corresponds so perfectly to his literature-fed fantasies:
“‘I am enchanted, believe me, / To die, thus, / In this medieval fashion, /
According to the best legends.’” Here an individual’s dream of fictive glory
proves antithetical to survival, a circumstance that Crane notes with ironic
mockery. At the same time, however, he emphasizes the almost dumbfounding
ability of the human imagination to shape significance and inspire action.
Formed by both literary and folk traditions in art, the youth’s ambitions
override adaptations that ordinarily guide behavior. In depicting the situation
as he does, divided between horror and derision, Crane offers a backhanded
tribute to the psychological power inherent in imaginative and aesthetic
constructs. Employing different imagery, Emily Dickinson makes a similar point
about the force of literature in her poem “A Word dropped careless on a Page”
(Poem 465). Art “may stimulate an eye” at a remove of “centuries,” influencing
thought, motivating action, and evoking emotion long after its “Maker” is dead.
Comparing these long-lasting effects to “infection” that “breeds,” Dickinson
conjures up the image of an epidemic: art resembles a fast-spreading contagious
disease. Carriers of infectious ideas and ideals, works of art are agents of
unstoppable transmission. Like Cervantes’s’ portrait of the idealistic but
lunatic Don Quixote, or Crane’s of a fatally romantic youth, Dickinson’s
metaphor elevates art by exploring its potentially sinister effects.
Transmitting its messages with subtlety and swiftness, art builds alternative
worlds so alluring that its audience occasionally may be drawn into maladaptive
modes of action. Because its influence operates in the arena of mind, moreover,
art is not susceptible to physical challenge or repulsion.
If the effects of art typically proved
deleterious to fitness, obviously, art-making activity long ago would have been
eliminated from the human repertoire of behaviors. Writers who represent cases
such as those just cited are using extreme instances to highlight the potency
and the importance of art, individually and communally, in human life: “the
whole race is a poet that writes down / The eccentric propositions of its fate”
(Stevens, “Men Made Out of Words”). Soothing and organizing interior tumult,
art helps to shape meaning and clarify options. To discover support for
Darwinian theories of art in the very artifacts under analysis may seem
solipsistic, but it is no different from using the insights of folk psychology
as rough-and-ready confirmation of Adaptationist theories of behavior. In and
of itself, such confirming evidence is insufficient, but it is nonetheless
useful in ongoing discussions of the evolutionary functions art may have served
in a variety of human environments. Since the virtual world constructed by each
work of art is in important ways unique, furthermore, fears that the introduction
of “rigorous empirical analysis” into literary methodology will reduce the
field to a mechanical gathering of statistics, or cognitive mapping, should be
allayed (in target article). “Impersonal, objective scrutiny” of the
psychological mechanisms to which art appeals will supplement, rather than
replace, detailed attention to singularities of aesthetic design and cultural
context shaping individual works—and the “phantom” but “sweeter” worlds those
works conjure.
Response to Joseph Carroll’s “An Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Study”
Michelle Scalise Sugiyama
Anthropology Department and
Institute of Cognitive and Decision Sciences
University of Oregon, Eugene 97403
Implicit in all evolutionary hypotheses
regarding the function of narrative is the assumption that stories transmit
information. Despite this, Carroll argues that narrative is not “didactic” in
function. The essence of his position is as follows: “The idea of art as a
source of information or exemplary lessons in conduct has some merit, but
information can be delivered in other ways more efficiently, and didacticism,
like novelty, leaves out too much of what is peculiar and specific to art,
while also excluding too many instances of art that could not plausibly be
described as didactic.”
Webster’s dictionary defines didactic
as “intended to convey instruction and information.” Storytelling clearly fits
this definition: it conveys information and, as a communicative act, it is
intentional (Sperber and Wilson). An inescapable conclusion follows: there are
no instances of storytelling that are not didactic.
Thus, the argument against “didacticism” is
largely semantic. For example, Carroll argues that “the arts fulfill a vital
adaptive function” by creating “an imaginative universe in which the forces at
work in the environment and inside the mind are brought into emotionally
meaningful relations to one another.” He adds that this “is not the same thing
as providing practically useful information or an objectively accurate map of
the external environment.” However, if the arts bring “the forces at work in
the environment and inside the mind into emotionally meaningful
relations to one another” (italics added), then the arts provide “practically
useful information” about “the external environment.” Meaning is information,
and information that is “vital” is both practical and useful. Moreover,
information need not be objective to be accurate or useful; it need only be
reliable. If information provided by imaginative universes did not reliably
correspond to the external environment, the arts could not “fulfill a vital
adaptive function.” The evaluative criteria that Carroll presents in an earlier
essay are grounded on just such a correspondence between the external
environment and imaginative universes: he critiques Kurtén’s and Auel’s
respective depictions of Neanderthals for being inconsistent with
archaeological evidence, arguing that “in fiction the rules of evidence and
logic do count. They are important elements in the integrity of conception in
the representation of the subject” (Literary Darwinism 173).
The conversation about didacticism is
really a conversation about design, as evinced by Carroll’s claim that
didacticism “leaves out too much of what is peculiar and specific to art.” He is
referring here to the subjective, emotional, aesthetic, and qualitative aspects
of art. I believe that conceptualizing narrative as a system for transmitting
adaptively useful information includes all of these qualities. The remainder of
this response will address these aspects of narrative design with respect to
what Carroll calls didacticism and what I call the information
transmission hypothesis (Scalise Sugiyama “Narrative as Social Mapping”). It
should be noted that Carroll’s paradigm embraces both art and narrative,
whereas my hypothesis refers exclusively to narrative.
There is no substantive conflict between
Carroll’s claim that literature “produces subjectively modulated images of the
world and of our experience in the world” and my claim that narrative is a
system for storing and transmitting adaptively useful information by simulating
the human environment. All information transmitted from one human to another is
“subjectively modulated” in that it is filtered first through the transmitter’s
and then through the receiver’s fitness interests, abilities, and experience (for
example, beliefs, desires, feelings). Hence, it goes without saying that any
adaptively useful information acquired through communication with a conspecific
is also subjective. Storytelling is triply so: (1) story content is inherently
biased by the priorities and prejudices of the storyteller (Scalise Sugiyama,
“On the Origins”); (2) each character embodies a unique set of abilities,
goals, and perspectives through which he/she views the world (Scalise Sugiyama
“Feminine Nature”); and (3) La Jalousie notwithstanding, narrative gives
us (subjectively modulated) access to the minds of others (Scalise Sugiyama,
“Feminine Nature”). Thus, narrative paradoxically gives us access to subjective
information (e.g., the “true” feelings, values, and opinions of others) that is
mediated by the subjectivity of the narrator. Obviously, this information must
be taken with a grain of salt because, to the extent that the narrator’s goals
conflict with the audience’s, it is likely to be biased. With its multiple
layers of subjectivity, then, narrative engages and may help calibrate
mechanisms for “considering the source” (Tooby and Cosmides, “The Past”)—that
is, for monitoring the conditions under which and the ways in which information
may be biased.
More provocative is Carroll’s claim that
art functions to organize “motivational systems disconnected from the immediate
promptings of instinct,” which is based on Wilson’s view of art as a response to uncertainty. Wilson argues that
one of the distinguishing characteristics of humans is their “high
intelligence” (Consilience 224) and that there has not been
sufficient time for algorithms to evolve that would enable humans to “cope with
the vastness of new contingent possibilities revealed by” this capacity (225). The
arts remedied this situation by making our ancestors feel that they had control
over the powerful, unpredictable forces that impinged on their daily survival:
sickness, famine, predators, enemies, weather. Significantly, Wilson asks whether—but
does not argue that--the arts are an adaptation: “If the arts are
steered by inborn rules of mental development, they are end products not just
of conventional history but also of genetic evolution. The question remains:
Were the genetic guides mere byproducts—epiphenomena—of that evolution, or were
they adaptations that directly improved survival and reproduction?” (224). He
does not proffer an answer to this question, and speaks only of the arts as having
“originated” (218), and having been “invented” (225) by humans.
Wilson’s argument that the arts provided a
remedy to the “confusion caused by intelligence” (225) hinges on high
intelligence having evolved rather recently and rapidly, both of which are
unlikely. Complex adaptations tend to evolve gradually (Dawkins, The Blind
Watchmaker; and Williams), and the trend toward encephalization is no
exception. It began roughly 2 mya with the emergence of H. habilis (mean
endocranial volume 630 cc), and continued with the emergence 1.8 mya of H.
erectus (mean endocranial volume 1000 cc), the emergence around 400,000 bp
of archaic H. sapiens (mean endocranial volume 1200 cc), and the
emergence around 130,000 bp of anatomically modern humans (mean endocranial volume
1560 cc) (Klein). Two million years is ample time for mechanisms mitigating the
effects of high intelligence to co-evolve—which would be necessary if high
intelligence did indeed impose severe fitness costs. (Strangely, in a
rumination that contradicts his own argument, Wilson posits that human capacity
to produce art might have been “perfected in small steps across millennia”
[227].) An organism that became paralyzed by confusion due to its awareness of
the uncontrollable forces of nature would simply not survive. This is the line
that Carroll takes, arguing that the arts are an “adaptive response to the
adaptive problem produced by the adaptive capacities of high intelligence.”
An alternative hypothesis, of course, is
that high intelligence is not behaviorally paralyzing. This is the view
articulated in the cognitive niche hypothesis (Tooby and DeVore). Like Wilson,
Tooby and DeVore argue that what distinguishes humans from other species is
their highly developed ability to represent contingently true information,
including hypothetical propositions. Tooby and DeVore refer to this ability as instrumental
intelligence, by which they mean the ability to create and maintain
cognitive cause-and-effect models of our environment. This view, like Wilson’s,
acknowledges that acquisition of this capacity was potentially costly, but
characterizes the problem differently: the circumstances under which a
contingently true proposition is valid may fluctuate; hence, the danger in
using contingently true information lies in applying it to the wrong
contingency. The solution to this problem is scope syntax—a sub-system for
monitoring and updating the limits within which contingently true information
is valid (Cosmides and Tooby; and Tooby and Cosmides, “”Does Beauty Build?”). In
contrast to Wilson, then, they see this capacity as empowering: cognitive
models are used as guides for prejudging which courses of action will lead to
which results. In short, instrumental intelligence enabled our ancestors to
plan. Far from paralyzing them, this ability allowed our hominid forbears to
tap hundreds of previously inaccessible resources—e.g., bone marrow, mollusks,
burrowing animals, plants with toxic compounds—through the use of tools. Archaeological
evidence supports the hypothesis that instrumental intelligence began
developing early in hominid prehistory: humans were using and making stone
tools by at least 2 mya.
Instrumental intelligence is also what
enables humans to tell stories. A story is a set of cause-and-effect representations
of possible human environments, possible human goals, possible strategies for
pursuing them, and possible outcomes of those strategies (Scalise Sugiyama,
“Food,” “Narrative as Social Mapping,” and “How an Interest”). In other words,
narrative is planning: “Imagery is the representation of perceptual information
in a format that resembles actual perceptual input” which “may serve to unlock,
for the purposes of planning, the same evolved mechanisms that are triggered by
an actual encounter with a situation displaying the imagined perceptual and
situational cues” (Tooby and Cosmides, “The Past” 416). Narrative is not a
solution to the problems inherent in representing contingently true
information; rather, the ability to represent contingently true information is
what makes narrative possible.
Also provocative is Carroll’s proposition
that “[m]eaning in art works through emotional and aesthetic impact.” This is a
reasonable claim that is almost surely true of much of the meaning in art, but
it is difficult to align with Carroll’s earlier claim that art functions to
organize “motivational systems disconnected from the immediate promptings of
instinct.” To see this, we need to understand how meaning is communicated
through emotional and aesthetic impact. Emotional and aesthetic systems are
motivational systems. Emotions respond to situational cues by signaling (i.e.,
conveying information to) cognitive structures relevant to addressing that
situation. For example, catching one’s mate in flagrante delicto activates
the emotion of sexual jealousy. This emotion, in turn, signals the suite of
mechanisms that respond to infidelity: “physiological processes are prepared
for violence; the goal of deterring, injuring, or murdering the rival emerges;
the goal of punishing or deserting the mate appears; the desire to make oneself
more competitively attractive appears” (Tooby and Cosmides, “The Past” 410),
and so on.
Aesthetic systems work in a similar
fashion, guiding behavior by causing us
to experience pleasure when we do something that increases our chances of
surviving and reproducing (e.g., sex, eating, sleeping). We find a given
object, phenomenon, or behavior attractive (i.e., beautiful, interesting, fun)
because it exhibits cues that, in ancestral environments, signaled that it
would have been advantageous to pay attention to it (Tooby and Cosmides,
“Does Beauty Build?”). Obviously, not
all of the activities we find pleasurable (e.g., sex, eating, sleeping)
function to convey meaning. But many do: activities such as babbling, chase
play, and stargazing furnish the mind with information requisite to the
development and/or calibration of specific adaptations (language, predator
evasion, and perception systems, respectively). Engaging in these activities
provides our brain circuitry “with the information, procedures, and
representations it needs to behave adaptively when called upon to do so” (Tooby
& Cosmides, “Does Beauty Build?” 16). Tooby and Cosmides argue that
engaging in fictional worlds may serve a similar function. This is very
different from arguing that the arts function to organize “motivational
systems disconnected from the immediate promptings of instinct.” The former
view posits that motivational systems prompt humans to engage in behaviors
(e.g., fiction) that organize adaptations. The latter view reverses the causal
order, positing that art behavior organizes motivational systems, presumably
providing them with the information they lack due to being “disconnected from
the immediate promptings of instinct.” This view begs the question, if
motivational systems must be organized by art behavior, what motivates humans
to engage in art behavior?
Additionally, it is not clear what it would
mean for motivational systems to be “disconnected from the immediate promptings
of instinct.” Motivational systems are instincts, if by “instinct” we
mean cognitive mechanisms designed by natural selection to solve an adaptive
problem. If motivational systems somehow became disconnected from the
“promptings of instinct”—that is, if they no longer responded to situational
cues—then they wouldn’t respond to simulations of those cues (e.g., art)
either.
Tooby and Cosmides’ discussion of the
relationship between emotion and planning (“The Past”) bears on the evaluative
aspect of narrative, by suggesting how engaging in narrative might calibrate
adaptations. They argue that one function of emotion may be to recalibrate
decision-rule weightings. Death, for example, “may involve guilt, grief, and
depression because of the problem of recalibration of weights on courses of
action. One may be haunted by guilt, meaning that courses of action
retrospectively judged to be erroneous may be replayed in imagination over and
over again, until the reweighting is accomplished” (“The Past” 416). They
further suggest that imagined courses of action may have the same effect. Although
they don’t mention narrative per se, imagined courses of action are, of
course, the foundation of narrative. On this view, then, certain of the
emotional responses evoked by a story may encourage us to replay the courses of
action it depicts (i.e., tell/listen to it repeatedly), thereby recalibrating
the weightings of the decision rules triggered by the story situation. This may
very well be what Carroll means when he proposes that the arts constitute an
“emotionally meaningful cognitive map [that] provides points of reference
within which humans adjust their sense of the relative value and significance
of things”: recalibrating can be likened to “adjusting,” and weightings can be
likened to “a sense of the relative value and significance of things.”
The most
parsimonious view at this point is that a story is a set of representations
that mimic situational cues that our motivational systems are designed to
respond to. Once engaged, these motivational systems trigger mechanisms
dedicated to processing the information contained in the represented cues. Although hypothetical, these
representations nevertheless contain reliable information about the physical
and social environment--including motivational systems (e.g., human emotional
responses). It doesn’t really matter whether we characterize this information
as “objective” or “subjective.” What matters is whether or not the information
is reliable—can it be used as if it were true? If so, and if possessing
and using such information can increase an individual’s fitness, then it falls
under the umbrella of “adaptively useful information.”
Given such an elegant system, Carroll’s claim that “information can be
delivered in other ways more efficiently” is surprising—especially since
ethnographic evidence suggests the opposite. Exploitation of the hunter-gather
niche demands exhaustive knowledge of a given habitat and its inhabitants,
including humans. This information must be retained to be useful: a delivery
system that does not embed this information in long-term memory cannot be said
to be efficient. There may be quicker ways of delivering information than
telling a story, but speed isn’t everything, and in modern foraging societies,
where there are no mass media, oral traditions are veritable repositories of
information critical to survival and reproduction.[47] The
efficiency of such a system and the significance of the information it
transmits may be hard to see through the informational effluents of recent
modern environments. Nevertheless, oral traditions were quite likely the first
information technology utilized by humans, and are the logical place to begin
looking for narrative design and function.
Literary Darwinism as Science and Myth
Roger Seamon
The program of
Darwinian literary study (DLS) that Joseph Carroll advances in “An Evolutionary
Paradigm for Literary Study” encompasses a number of projects whose
relationships are unclear, whose ambitions are unrealizable, and whose
interpretive power is weak. However, the most disturbing aspect of the project
is that it depends on misunderstanding the nature of literary study.
Literary study is not
now, and never has been, a progressive science whose aim is “generating new knowledge.”
in the form of scientific theories; its purpose is to carry on a literary
tradition, whose remoteness, of one kind or another, presents a barrier to that
aim. The study of Latin and Greek literature is the model. Literary study
establishes texts, tries to determine meanings in historical context, and
produces narratives based on those meanings. The purpose of literary study is
the transmission, transformation, and even creation of literary
traditions—think of F. O. Matthiessen’s American Renaissance.
Literary study is not “about” those traditions, it is a constitutive part of
the them. The scholar thus has a very different relationship to literary works
than a scientist, who seeks causal explanations rather than interpretations and
narratives. Literary scholarship is an enterprise that has long done its work
more or less well, and the current danger to the field is not the absence of a
unifying scientific theory but the replacement of classic literary works and
major traditions with “cultural texts” that may not even be literature at all.
The crisis in literary
study that Jonathan Gottschall traces to “a methodological failure to produce
empirically valid and progressive forms of knowledge” (quoted by Carroll) is,
in fact, a minor part of the tradition of literary study itself. When
vernacular literatures were introduced to the curriculum of research
universities in the late nineteenth century they had to overcome the objection
that literature in one’s native language, unlike the classics, did not require
disciplinary study. Since vernacular works were addressed to and readily
understood by educated adults, what would one be tested on—one’s taste? To
counter these objections the literary scholars introduced and made central to
the discipline the history of modern languages, which yielded “laws,” and Anglo-Saxon.
As F. W. Bateson says: “When we came into being some seventy years ago the
superimposition of Eng. Lang. on Eng. Lit. . . . was tactically necessary to
meet the objection that Eng. Lit. per
se would be a ‘soft option’” (222).
The worry that
motivated this initial defensive effort has been felt ever since, and it is
science that has usually been called to the rescue. In 1893 Richard Green
Moulton published Shakespeare as a
Dramatic Artist; a Popular Illustration of the Principles of Scientific
Criticism, and New Criticism was based, in part, on the linguistic
theories of Russian Formalism. Psychoanalytic theories, Marxism, structural
linguistics and other alleged or actual sciences have also been used to make
scientific claims for literary study. The case for making it a science was made
most forcefully by Northrop Frye in the “Polemical Introduction” to his Anatomy of Criticism, and Frye
offered his own archetypal theory. Three decades later Jonathan Culler said
that structuralist literary theory was an attempt to “revitalize criticism and
free it from an exclusively interpretive role[by] developing a programme which
would justify it as a mode of knowledge” (viii). Nothing like a science of literature
emerged from these efforts., and DLS will, I believe, meet the same fate as
earlier efforts to make literary study a science.
What, then, is DLS? Consider
Carroll’s claim that DLS has “an obligation to situate texts and critical
histories in the broader context of evolutionary social science, connecting
local critical perceptions with general principles of literary theory, and
integrating these principles with principles of psychology, linguistics, and
anthropology.” That is a recipe for a hodge-podge of theories within theories,
and is of a piece with the strange ambition that animates the project, to
create “an integrated body of knowledge extending in an unbroken chain of
material causation from the lowest level of subatomic particles to the highest
levels of cultural imagination.” The cosmologists can’t yet get past the first
few milliseconds, but never mind, it will soon smooth sailing from the big bang
to James Joyce. Although this is absurd as a scientific project, there is an
understandable ambition behind it.
Since the rise of
science, non-believing intellectuals have produced grand narratives that claim
to be based on, or compatible with, science ,and which offer comprehensive
accounts of human existence. These myths, as I shall call them, are meant to
replace the Christian story. Hegel’s Phenomenology
of Spirit is the earliest such myth; Marx and Freud followed in his
wake, and that is what Carroll and others hope for from Darwin. Carroll wrote
in 2002 that “we are on the verge of synthesizing [the] elements” necessary for
a “full and adequate conception of human nature” (“Emerging Research Program”
1). That is what myths do, but not science, since “human nature” is a folk
psychological concept. However, if history is any guide, it is precisely as
myth that DLS might find its way into the curriculum as part of what Carroll
calls “the practical work of interpretive criticism.”
There are precedents
for this. What happens is that literary scholars appropriate scientific
vocabularies to offer interpretations
rather than scientific theories,
and, despite appearances, these are completely different enterprises. Let me
explain.
Literary interpreters
routinely talk about the themes of literary works, and these themes connect
elements in the work to concerns that resonate with us and our students. Thus,
we might speak of the theme of barbarism and civilization in Othello. Talking about literary
works this way makes them mean something to us, whatever they may have meant to
their original audience. But themes are, as it were, optional (one can
understand Othello perfectly
well without ever thinking about civilization and barbarism), and therefore
weak academically in the research environment, and so academic literary
interpreters have, since the 1930s, used vocabularies taken from various real
or putative sciences as a way of making their interpretations look scientific
and therefore necessary if one is to really
understand literary works.[48]
Linguistics, psychology, anthropology, and sociology have been the main sources
of these interpretations.[49] However,
offering an explanation of Othello’s actions in Darwinian terms is not a
scientific explanation but a rhetorical move whose aim is to enhance the value
of both Shakespeare and Darwinism by showing that a masterpiece is intuitively
deep about human nature and that Darwinian science is able to (finally) reveal
a deep truth about a great work. Neither claim is true, but the method has
worked for Marxists, Freudians, Jungians, structuralists and others, so why not
for Darwinians? The answer to that question is bleak, but that is greatly to
Darwinism’s credit. How so?
Darwinism, as an
interpretive schema, has the virtue of being based on a true theory, but it
will have a very short run in academia, because as an interpretation of life it
is dull and empty of meaning. Freud offers a conflict-ridden account of
individual development and its discontents, and Marx provides us with a
brilliant story about how society develops through class struggle and how
social injustice is maintained. There is a “fall” in both stories, which
accounts for human suffering, and both offer a vision of the future to guide
us, the admittedly modest replacement of some id by the ego and, much more
grandly, a classless society.
What does Darwinism
offer along these lines? The Darwinian vision is something like Eliot’s “birth,
copulation, and death,” the universals that are part of our animal inheritance
plus a few of our own, although as we find language, song, and tool use in
other animals, our uniqueness dims. Where is the drama that successful
interpretations of human life offer, or even a distinctive human nature? Darwinism
will fail as an interpretive schema because it is mythically impoverished. Darwin
tells us an awful truth; we are headed nowhere special without a purpose or a
compass.[50] That
is why the Darwinians will be lucky even to achieve a place in those
collections of approaches that Carroll sees as just a small step on the way to
hegemony and which tend to be hospices for expiring interpretive schemas.
Perhaps the oddest of
Carroll’s claims for DLS is that in the consilient academy “humanistic
sensitivity to the fine shades of tone and style in literary works will have
blended seamlessly with a rigorous empirical analysis of cognitive mechanisms,
and a facility in writing elegantly nuanced prose will mingle happily with the
severe logic of a quantitative methodology. Scholars and scientists occupied
with literary study will balance easy grace between impersonal, objective scrutiny
of science and a passionate humanistic responsiveness” (32). This is bizarre—or
perhaps a joke? It never has been, is not now, and never will be the case that
academics will routinely produce elegantly nuanced prose (of course a few do). Indeed,
such prose is usually deprecated as appropriate to what Northrop Frye called
“public critics,” whose job is to convey through lively plot summary and
evocative language the feel of literary works so that the audience of common
readers can get some sense of whether or not they might like the book. That
scientists will become literary scholars and develop a talent that literary
folk reject is an even wilder surmise. If this is the aim of the Darwinian
program it is certain that it will not be achieved.
Nothing I have said
denies that perhaps some day scientists will understand the brain mechanisms
that underlie irony, metaphor and other aspects of literature, and why such
aspects of language were adaptive (although that seems immensely more difficult).
At the moment, however, there seems to be merely a plethora of speculations. Some
think there is a story module, while William Ramsey says of what he calls
narrative intelligence, "[t]he processing is highly distributed throughout
the entire system, and there are no task‑specific modules, discrete
symbols or explicit rules that govern the operations” (cited by Herman). If the
science is still so uncertain, many of Carroll’s claims are very premature. But
even were the scientists to find out what mechanisms enable us to tell and
understand stories, and how that behavior is an adaptation, the theories would
have no bearing on literary study, just as theories about the mechanisms that
enable outfielders to track fly balls do not shed any light on or enhance
appreciation of baseball. And shedding light on and enhancing the appreciation
of literary works and traditions are what literary study does and should do.
Good and Bad Reductionism: Acknowledging the Power of Culture
Edward Slingerland
University of British Columbia
As someone who has
written at length on the need for vertical integration or consilience between
the natural sciences and the humanities, I am obviously in agreement with the
majority of Carroll’s argument. I particularly think it is important to recognize,
as Carroll notes, that any work in academia worth its salt is “reductive” in
some respect—that is, seeks to explain a particular phenomenon in terms of more
basic, general principles. The common tendency in the humanities to use
“reductionistic” as a peremptory term of dismissal is therefore entirely
unjustified. I do think, however, that it is important to distinguish between
“good” and “bad” forms of reductionism, and to make it clear that consilience,
properly understood, involves an ongoing respect for the relative autonomy of
the levels of explanation studied by the humanities. I do not think that this
is something with which Carroll would disagree, but at points in his essay his
rhetoric suggests otherwise. If those of us who support evolutionary approaches
to the humanities wish to win broader acceptance among our colleagues, it is
incumbent upon us to make it clear that consilience does not entail—as many
humanists fear it does—collapsing humanities departments into biology
departments, denying the significance of human-level truths, or reducing human
culture to a mechanistically-expressed phenotypic trait.
Carroll notes the
existence of a group of scholars interested in cognitive approaches to
literature who nonetheless seem determined to distance themselves from literary
Darwinism. This is, on the face of it, rather puzzling: the human cognitive
system is a product of evolution, so it is hard to imagine why someone
interested in human cognition would have an allergy to evolutionary theory. No doubt
some of this leeriness results from a visceral aversion liberal intellectuals
tend to exhibit toward any mention of Darwinism or evolution: in my experience,
the leap from “Darwinism” to “Nazism” or “eugenics” is an almost Pavlovian
response for most humanists, and it takes some work to overcome this
indefensible and intellectually lazy response. In addition, as I have argued
elsewhere, a powerful source of resistance to applying evolutionary theory to
human beings is our innate mind-body dualism (a product of our Theory of Mind):
we are comfortable talking about non-human animal behavior or “merely physical”
aspects of human beings (our organs, our limbs) in evolutionary terms, but the
mind and its products strike us as being qualitatively different in some way.
In this sense, it could be said that we are built by evolution to have trouble
believing in evolution as a universal explanatory framework. The combination of
our innate resistance to physicalism and the historically-conditioned kneejerk
reaction against Darwin means that any attempt to advance literary Darwinism is
going to be an uphill battle.
One way to make
progress in this battle is to make it clear that vertically integration does not
entail eliminative or “greedy” reductionism, whereby the heuristic importance
and relative autonomy of higher-level entities is denied. A glance at the
natural sciences allows us to get a good grasp of what “good” reductionism
looks like. Neuroscience is dependent upon organic chemistry, which in turn is
dependent upon physical chemistry, which in turn is dependent on physics. The
nature of this dependence is such that lower levels of explanation exert an
important constraining function on the higher levels. A hypothesis in organic
chemistry that violates everything that we think we know about physical
chemistry is likely to be rejected out of hand; if not, it would require a
complete rethinking of physical chemistry. The argument behind vertical
integration is that the levels of explanation studies by the humanities need to
be plugged into their proper place at the top of this hierarchy of explanation,
and be subjected to the same constraint of overall “consilience.” At the same
time, this does not entail the disappearance of human-level disciplines, or
their absorption into lower levels, because as we move up the explanatory chain
we witness the emergence of new heuristic entities, which possess their own
novel organizational principles. Organic chemistry has not been replaced by
quantum physics because organic molecules have a set of emergent properties,
and are governed by a set of emergent principles, that are simply not
predictable or tractable from the perspective of quantum physics. This is why
biology and chemistry departments continue to enjoy autonomy from physics
departments, and why humanities departments are not going anywhere even if the
academy were to fully embrace vertical integration.
At many points in his
essay, this seems to be what Carroll is arguing with regard to evolutionary
psychology and the study of literature: theories that we propose about reader
response or the functioning of particular rhetorical forms need to be informed
and constrained by what we know about how the human mind works. “Trying to
isolate literary study from psychological and historical generalizations is a
sophistical maneuver,” he observes, “that will not stand against the simplest
appeal to factual evidence.” He rightly points out that the key flaw common to
most of the currently dominant approaches to literature is that they “emphasize
the exclusively cultural character of symbolic constructs,” and therefore
create an intellectual environment in which natural scientific knowledge about
human nature or cognition “can exercise no constraining force on culture.” One immediate
and important affect of adopting a vertically-integrated stance to the
humanities would be the elimination of a variety of widely-believed but
empirically indefensible views about human cognition and culture—such as the
“blank slate” view of human nature or the ideal of disembodied reason—and
Carroll notes that this is an important “negative” service to be performed by
literary Darwinism: “If evolutionary literary study did nothing more than clear
away…distorting theoretical impedimenta…[it] would have performed a valuable
service.” In addition, of course, there is also an important positive
dimension: once literature is placed in its proper relationship to lower levels
of explanation, such as evolutionary theory or cognitive science, a plethora of
new hypotheses about literature immediately suggest themselves, accompanied by
a powerful new explanatory framework and set of vocabulary.
So far, so good. My
one concern about Carroll’s presentation of his position, however, is that one
sometimes gets the sense that he is advocating the stronger, “biology subsumes
all” position that humanists rightly want nothing to do with. Examples of
Carroll’s sometimes troubling rhetoric include his characterization of literary
Darwinism’s goal as “sweep[ing] past inclusion” in traditional institutional
structures and “subsum[ing] all other possible approaches to literary study,”
as well as his metaphor of literary Darwinism as a city core “swallow[ing] up”
outlying enclaves in an inexorable advance. Jettisoning strong forms of social
constructivism would indeed mark an important “shift” in our “frame of
interpretation,” and bringing evolutionary theory and cognitive science to bear
on literary studies in an explicit and systematic way would mark a real
revolution in literary studies methodology and rhetoric. However, because
fields such as literary studies tend to concern themselves overwhelmingly with
emergent structures and idiosyncratic cultural histories, it is not clear to me
that adopting a vertically-integrated perspective would have such a global and
dramatic effect on the day-to-day work of most literary scholars. This is
particularly the case when one recognizes, as Carroll does, that many literary
scholars in fact implicitly share many of the assumptions of a vertically-integrated
approach—such as important commonalities in human nature, universality in
narrative forms, etc.—even if they deny these commonalities in their rhetorical
and theoretical posturing.
I have a colleague
whose research interest focuses on the intersection of poetics and political
patronage, as manifested in the production of official poetry anthologies. She
often asks me why someone like her would care about vertical integration. One
answer is that adopting a vertically-integrated perspective—for instance,
learning something about evolutionary psychology and cognitive science and
taking it seriously in her work—might very well, as Carroll notes, involve an
important shift in her overall interpretative framework. The typical
Foucaultian framework we all imbibed in graduate school encourages her to see
her work as documenting the manner in which aesthetics is primarily driven by
politics and power, with “beauty” revealed as no more than culturally-specific
construction. An evolutionary framework might lead her to focus more on
coalition-formation, prosociality, and aesthetic forms as in-group markers—an
important advance over Foucault because it would allow her to plug her work
into a much broader and more powerful explanatory framework, one that also has
the wonderful virtue of being empirically plausible.
However, it is also
important to acknowledge that 90% of her work is concerned with the specifics
of how this particular person commissioned this particular poetry
anthology, and how this historical event influenced some very culturally- and
linguistically-specific forms of poetic expression. Evolutionary theory does
not speak directly to these issues. Carroll rightly criticizes Eugene Goodheart
and the common move to metaphysical dualism that argues that, while science
studies regularities of dumb nature, the humanities study the ontologically
unique and unpredictable movements of the mysterious human Geist. If the
humanities were only concerned with uniqueness they would not represent academic
disciplines—literary study would be no more than an exercise in stamp
collecting. Nevertheless, the task of explaining and understanding literature
often operates at a such a high level of emergent specificity that evolutionary
psychology is only marginally more relevant than quantum mechanics, and this is
why traditional forms of literary study will continue to function more or less
autonomously even within a vertically-integrated framework. Familiarity with
the literature on coalition-formation and prosociality is not going to tell my
colleague anything about the specific aesthetic choices made by competing
factions of poets, and this is one of the central questions that she is
interested in answering. Again, I don’t think that Carroll would necessarily
disagree with any of this, but it would behoove him to make it clearer to his
colleagues that, while consilience would provide an important new explanatory
framework within which literary studies could operate, it does not necessarily
entail radical alterations in one’s everyday methodology, vocabulary or focus
of interest. Literary scholars do not need to stop talking about history and
genre, or confine themselves only to terms and concepts drawn from evolutionary
psychology.
A related point is
that Carroll also at times gives the impression that he views culture as a
more-or-less direct expression of innate human psychological mechanisms—à la
E.O. Wilson’s (in)famous metaphor of the human brain as “an exposed negative
waiting to be dipped in developer fluid” (Sociobiology 156)—rather than
a potentially autonomous force in its own right. It is true that, as Carroll
notes, “culture translates human nature in social norms and shared imaginative
structures,” but it is also important to recognize that culture regularly transforms
human nature and cognition in important ways. One doesn’t have to be a
wild-eyed social constructivist to acknowledge this point—much of the most
interesting recent work in evolutionary psychology and embodied cognition has
focused on the co-evolution of human cognition and culture—but the
overall thrust of Carroll’s argument leaves one with the impression that all
significant structure comes from innate human nature, and that cultural
variation is a mere epiphenomenon. I fear that one unfortunate effect of many
recent attempts to bring a robust conception of human nature back to the fore
is the creation—perhaps often unintended—of a false dichotomy between nature
and nurture: that the only alternatives are embracing full-blown social constructivism
or believing in a single, universal human nature that merely gets “translated”
into various cultures. In fact, a vertically-integrated, embodied approach to
human culture—one fundamentally informed by evolutionary theory and the latest
discoveries in cognitive science—can take us beyond such dichotomies. The work
of scholars such as Pete Richardson and Rob Boyd has shown how cultural forms
themselves are subject to a kind of evolution, constrained by the structures of
human cognition but also exerting their own independent force. In fact,
cultural evolution may have driven human genetic evolution, favoring our
big brains, linguistic skills, and ultra-sociality, the three hallmarks of
our species. Similarly, conceptual metaphor and blending theory give us
very specific models for understanding how universal, innate human cognitive
patterns can get projected into new domains or combined to generate entirely
novel, emergent structures. Human cognitive fluidity, ratcheted up over time by cultural
entrenchment, can shape human emotions, desires and perception in quite novel
and idiosyncratic ways—from the subtle Japanese aesthetic sentiment of mono
no aware (lit. “the sorrow of things”) to the sort of “cultivated needs”
explored in depth by theorists such as Pierre Bourdieu.
Carroll does not
explicitly deny the importance of such work, and does make passing reference to
cognitive fluidity and cognitive linguistics. More of an acknowledgement of how
culture can play an active role in reshaping human nature, however, would go a
long way toward winning over skeptical humanists—for whom the dazzling variety
of various human cultures and the nuances of specific cultural products are the
most salient features of human beings—and help to bring the literary Darwinians
in from the jungles of their guerilla war.
Literature as Self-Engineering: An Evolutionary Hypothesis
David Livingstone Smith
“Literature always anticipates life. It
does not copy it, but moulds it to its purpose”
– Oscar Wilde
Joseph Carroll points out in his target
article that there is not yet a consensus about the role of literature and the
other arts in human evolution. It is note even clear whether or not the art has
an adaptive function. If art is adaptive, there must be a reproductively
significant problem for which it was, and perhaps still is, a solution. But
what is this problem, and how art provide a solution for it? Answering this
question should be at the top of the agenda of anyone seriously interested in a
Darwinian approach to literary studies. Carroll takes up the challenge, and
after surveying the main contenders – the hypotheses offered by Pinker, Miller,
Dissanayake and Boyd – he concludes that Edmund O. Wilson’s hypothesis about
the evolution of art is the most promising option currently on the table. While
I am sympathetic with Carroll’s aim, I have doubts about the adequacy and
coherence of Wilson’s hypothesis. In this commentary, I will set out what I
think is wrong with Wilson’s approach, and then go on to gesture towards an
alternative that promises to give a more adequate account of the adaptive
function of literature.
Wilson holds art is an adaptation: a
solution to a problem in living rather than a mere byproduct of evolution, and
that as such, it contributed directly to the survival and reproductive success
of our prehistoric ancestors. On this view, the adaptive problem for which art
supplied a solution was a consequence of the evolution of the human brain. Our
“extremely high intelligence, language, culture, and reliance on long-term
social contracts…gave early Homo sapiens
a decisive edge over all competing animal species, but they also extracted a
price we continue to pay, composed of a shocking recognition of the self, of
the finiteness of personal existence, and of the chaos of the environment” thus
rendering us “psychological exiles” (224-25). In response to this crisis of
awareness, early human beings invented the arts to “express and control through
magic the abundance of the environment, the power of solidarity, and
other forces in their lives that mattered most to survival and reproduction…. The
arts still perform this primal function, and in much the same ancient way”
(225-26, emphasis added).
As enticing as this hypothesis may seem, it
is difficult, if not impossible, to reconcile Wilson’s claim that art is an
adaptation with his subsequent claim that art is magic. Magic does not enhance
reproductive success, nor does it help us to live longer, attract more fertile
mates, or have healthier offspring. Although one might argue that magical
practices and beliefs provide a reproductive advantage by decreasing stress,
this explanation does not seem credible. The costs of art – the time, resources
and energy invested in artistic production – would have been unlikely to
outweigh what is presumably a relatively small advantage provided by
stress-reduction. Also, quite apart from its specifically biological
shortcomings, the conjecture that art began and continues to function as a
magical way to control the environment strikes me as implausible. It seems to
me that most of us seem to be blissfully oblivious to the menacing shadow of
mortality, and do not cling to art to soothe our existential pain or provide an
illusion of control in a chaotic and hazardous world.
If imaginative culture is an adaptation it
must have made a significant difference to the material conditions of the lives
of prehistoric men and women. But how did it do this? Imaginary culture
presupposes the capacity for imagination, so in order to answer this question
we will need to understand the adaptive function of imagination simpliciter.
There are a dozen or more conceptions of imagination scattered through the
scientific and philosophical literature, but for the purpose of this analysis
we can start with a conception of it as “the ability to think of whatever
one acknowledges as possible in the spatio-temporal world” (Stevenson 241).
Prior to the evolution of the capacity for imagination, our ancestors’ minds
must have been as rigidly bound to the deliverances of their sense organs as
the minds of nonhuman primates are today. Presumably, there was a time when our
ancestors believed only what they could see, touch, taste, smell or hear. However,
once their brains evolved the cognitive horsepower to move across the landscape
of thought from the observed to the unobserved, they became able to make
inductive inferences about the world, and this newfound capacity enabled them
to anticipate a whole range of dangers and opportunities that would otherwise
have remained beyond their ken.
Cognitive traits are invisible to natural selection unless they have a
reproductively significant impact on behavior, and thought produces behavior
only if it is conjoined with belief. So, in order for imaginative thought to be
selected into their cognitive repertoire, early human beings had to negotiate
the tricky transition from operating on the principle of “seeing is believing”
to the principle of “seeing with the mind’s eye is believing”. How did this
happen? It seems likely that the brain system responsible for inferential
thought co-opted the representational systems previously dedicated to the sense
organs. This would account for an important feature of imagination: its qualitative,
quasi-sensory character. It is precisely this feature of imagination that
supplies its special motivating power.
These considerations bring us to a second
conception of imagination as “the ability to entertain mental images”
(Stevenson 243). It is, as Aquinas put it almost eight hundred years ago, “a
creative activity, whereby the imagination forms for itself an image of
something absent, or something perhaps never seen” (I 85 ad 3). As useful as this ability was, it left the human mind with a
critical vulnerability. From this point onward, fantasy and reality would
compete for control of human behavior. The mind’s tendency to be swept along by
fantasy was the price that our species paid for acquiring the ability to make
inductive inferences.
Like all biological functions, imagination
can either succeed or fail to achieve its adaptive purpose; it succeeds when an
envisaged possibility turns out to be an actuality, and it fails when what is
imagined does not mesh with how things really are. This brings us to a third
definition of imagination as “the ability to think of something which the
subject believes to be real, but which is not real” (Stevenson 242). There
is an obvious connection between the failure of imagination to achieve its
purpose and the literary enterprise. After all, literature traffics in fiction:
literary narratives that do not represent the world precisely as it is. It was
this contrast between reality and fiction that inspired Plato’s fulminations
against poetry in The Republic and David Hume’s characterization of
poets as “liars by profession” who “endeavor to give an air of truth to their
fictions” in his Treatise of Human Nature (87). Shakespeare, too, was
alert to the epistemically dissonant character of poetry:
The poet’s eye, in a fine frenzy rolling,
Doth glance from heaven to earth, from
earth to heaven;
And as imagination bodies forth
The forms of things unknown, the poet’s pen
Turns them to shapes and gives to
airy nothing
A local habitation and a name (Wordsworth
edition, V, 1.12-17)
These reflections seem to suggest that literature is nothing but a
disease of imagination, but this conclusion would be too hasty. There is a
clear distinction between the purpose of imagination and the purpose of
literature. Imagination aims to represent the world as it really is. But
literature has a different aim: its purpose is to misrepresent the world. Just
as imagination fails when it does not manage to represent the world accurately,
literature fails when it represents the world too accurately. The point of
literature is not to describe the world as it is, but to artfully misrepresent
it in ways that transform our relationship with reality, and thereby transform
our behavior. The function of literature is to shape human action.
To explore this conjecture further, we need
to take seriously Hume’s description of the poet-as-liar. Although lying is a
distinctively human form of deception, non-verbal deception pervades the
natural world. From the misleading chemical signals purveyed by the humble
virus, to the sophisticated Machiavellian maneuvers of chimpanzees, living
things seem intent on pulling the wool over one another’s eyes. The purpose of
deception is to manipulate the behavior of others to one’s own advantage.
Consequently, successful deceivers have an edge in the struggle for existence.
We human animals are natural born liars too, and our lies have the same
biological purpose as the deceptive strategies of non-human organisms (for a
more detailed account see my book Why We Lie: The Evolutionary Roots of
Deception and the Unconscious Mind).
Unlike other animals, human beings also have the ability to lie to
themselves. Although self-deception appears disadvantageous, it may have a
biological purpose. According to the hypothesis first advanced by the
sociobiologist Robert Trivers “the overriding function of self-deception is the more fluid
deception of others. That is,
hiding aspects of reality from the conscious mind also hides these aspects more
deeply from others” (“Introduction” vii). Self-deception is an adjunct to
interpersonal deception, and helps us to reap the advantages accrued from
deceiving our conspecifics. If Trivers is right, self-deception is a
psychological trait that succeeds when it disrupts our contact with reality in
the service of a more pressing goal – the goal of manipulating others to serve
one’s interests.
Deceiving others is not the only contribution that
self-deception makes to our lives. I argued in The Most Dangerous Animal
that prehistoric hominins almost certainly had an innate, biologically
determined aversion to spilling the blood of community members, but no
reservations about killing their neighbors to acquire their resources. However,
thanks to the expansion of the human brain, our ancestors eventually became
capable of entertaining concepts, including the concept of a human being. This
dawning awareness precipitated a psychological conflict between the warlike
urge to kill other human beings, bred into them by millions of years of
evolution, and inhibitions against violence flowing from the recognition of the
human status of their neighbors – their membership in an extended human
“community” (for a similar argument, see Roscoe). So, to be psychologically
capable of butchering other human beings, our ancestors had to find a way to
override their natural inhibitions against killing, and they seem to have
accomplished this by exploiting the psychological vulnerability created by the
evolution of imagination. They recruited the resources of imaginative culture
to generate evocative images depicting their neighbors as less than human, and
therefore as lying outside the moral universe. Although propaganda is regarded
today as a degenerate form of literature, it may have once been a primary
function of story telling. If I am right, literature originated as a form of self-engineering,
a method for manipulating our own behavioral dispositions by canalizing deep,
biologically rooted passions to produce novel forms of behavior. As we have
seen from the case of war, some of these behaviors were adaptive. Others, such
as voluntary celibacy, self-mutilation and human sacrifice, were not.
In conclusion, I think that Wilson correctly stressed the intimate tie
between art and behavioral flexibility, but his account of that relationship
needs to be inverted. Behavioral flexibility was the consequence rather than
the cause of the evolution of art. Arguably, even today, the role of art is to
structure human behavior, and when contemporary human beings find themselves moved
by a poem, a novel or a fine theatrical performance, they experience a faint
glimmer of the primal power of literature to move us to action.
The Evolutionary Paradigm: the View from Film Studies
Murray Smith, University of Kent
In his commentary on the emerging paradigm
of evolutionary literary studies, Joseph Carroll paints a compelling picture of
a vibrant new field of enquiry. He presents a brilliant synthesis of key
debates and positions within evolutionary theory, paying detailed attention to
the advocates as well as the assailants of an evolutionary perspective on the
arts, in a manner which is at once trenchant, lucid and nuanced. He also weaves
in discussion of more general and central issues in literary theory, such as
the relationship between generalization and the particular work, and the nature
of “reduction.” For all these reasons, the essay ought to be of great interest
not only to card-carrying evolutionists and fellow-travellers, but to anyone
interested in literary theory as such. Carroll has done a service to literary
studies in “cognitively mapping” evolutionary theory, to use one of his own
central terms, in such clear and engaging terms.
But nobody is perfect. There are a number
of issues raised by Carroll on which more needs to be said, as I am sure
Carroll would be the first to acknowledge. One of the indirect virtues of the
evolutionary paradigm is that it brings humanistic enquiry into the arts into
closer dialogue with the social and natural sciences, and with the “naturalistic”
strand of contemporary philosophy. This genuine interdisciplinarity – as
distinct from the routine quality of a great deal of work in the humanities
that flies under the flag of interdisciplinarity – imposes a lot of hard
reflection on epistemological matters, and raises the standard of argument.
Whatever the fate of evolutionary theory as a whole and the particular schools
of thought within it, literary studies can only benefit from engagement with
the ethos and methods of the sciences, in the spirit urged by Carroll, even as
it retains a distinct identity.
In describing the current state of play
within literary studies, Carroll discusses the relationship between the
relatively well-established school of “cognitive poetics,” and the more recent
wave of evolutionary literary theory. A parallel situation exists within film
studies: “cognitive film theory” has established itself as a minority but
inflential voice within the discipline, consolidating itself through an
academic society, specialist conferences and journal issues, and a steady
stream of publications. “Evolutionary cognitivism” exists as a minority within
that minority, and a controversial one to boot. As in literary so in film
studies in this respect: all evolutionists are cognitivists, but not all cognitivists
are evolutionists.
Nature and culture
The most influential conception of the relationship between the natural
and cultural, certainly within the humanities, is given usefully stark
expression by Fredric Jameson in the passage quoted by Carroll: “nature is gone
for good.” One of the more important philosophical expressions of this idea is
due to Hegel, who conceives of human subjectivity (Geist) as in a state
of “alienation” from the natural order. Because human beings have the capacity
to reflect upon their impulses and instinctive reactions, they become detached
from the natural world in which no such reflection is found. This argument is
echoed uncannily in the passages quoted by Carroll from E.O. Wilson’s Consilience,
where Wilson speaks of the centrality of “instinct” to the behaviour of all
animal species bar human beings, and the human “psychological exile” that this
entails. Wilson’s formulation points the way towards a “naturalized”
alternative to Hegelian “alienation,” an alternative developed by Carroll in
his essay. On this alternative conception, culture is not alienated from or
opposed to nature, but recognized as a part of nature – specifically a crucial
part of that bit of the natural world we call “human nature.” As Carroll notes,
humans can survive and develop physiologically outside of a cultural setting,
as in the case of feral children, but such children are radically incomplete as
human beings. The natural developmental course of a human child involves
development and maturation through cultural practices, including language; it
thus makes no sense to place culture outside of the domain of nature when it
comes to humans.
Indeed, recent research shows that we are
not the only species to possess culture, if by “culture” we mean practices (“suites of local traditions” – [Whiten
PP #]] which are specific to particular communities within a species,
transmitted mimetically across generations within these communities rather than
genetically. Chimpanzees display cultural variation across a wide range of
behaviours, including termite harvesting and hand-clasping related to grooming (Whiten, de Waal).
Similarly, we ought to be cautious in how we use the concept of “instinct” to
draw the line between humans and other animal species. Are all non-human
animals equally driven by instinct pure and simple ? Don’t some animals –
primates and dolphins perhaps – possess powers of deliberation of a different
order to insects ? Within philosophy of mind, a debate now exists over the
notion of “animal rationality,” recognizing the possibility and reality that at
least certain species possess sufficient mental complexity that their behaviour
cannot be adequately understood through “instinct” alone. [Similarly, “proto-morality”
has been identified among some non-human primates.] Thus in respect of both
culture and rationality [and even morality] there is greater continuity between
humans and other species than traditional conceptions of human being have
acknowledged; resistance to this idea only demonstrates the extent to which the
implications of Darwin’s theories have still not been properly digested. It
doesn’t follow from these points about non-human culture and rationality that
there is not a gulf separating human and non-human psychology. Culture surely is
fundamentally important to human development and flourishing in a way that it
is not even for the most sophisticated non-human species. But the continuity of
species underlines the fact that culture needs to be understood as an aspect of
nature, one that plays an especially important role for the human species. Far
from diminishing or undervaluing what makes humans distinctive in the animal
world, approaching humans naturalistically – seeing our “species-typical”
characteristics as a part of the natural world – allows us to obtain a more
precise understanding of human nature and the human condition, of that “psychological
exile” of which Wilson writes.
One upshot of this is that humans naturally
understand the world from within a particular cultural perpective. Even that
small community of humans we know as “scientists,” part of whose job it is to
stand outside of any such perspective and obtain the “view from nowhere” (Nagel [[PP #]), will in
their everyday dealings view the world in this fashion. And this is the stuff
of the humanities – of literature, film, and the other arts, which all form
part of and arise from the fabric of particular cultures: just as there no
fully-flourishing “non-cultural” humans, so there are no cases of genuinely
non-cultural art works. (And logically speaking, why shouldn’t there be?) The
questions which humanists are thus charged with asking – concerning the form,
meaning and value of works of art – will thus never be answered in a fully
satisfying manner at the universal level alone. It is thus crucial that
Carroll’s model for an evolutionary form of literary criticism involves the integration
of the universal, the cultural, and indeed the individual levels of analysis.
Denuded of these more proximate and finer-grained layers, an analysis of a
literary work distilling only its universal components will feel abstract and
incomplete; a multi-level account, combining all three layers, promises the
richest and most satisfying account of all.
Grand theory and the “middle level”
In discussing the various modes of literary
criticism of the last half-century or so, Carroll posits a continuum from
impressionistic commentary to the systematic, theory-driven analysis of texts.
Carroll is right to heap scorn on anti-theoretical particularism, at least as
an all-encompassing account of literary studies; and elsewhere in his essay,
equally justified in questioning the easy-going pluralism of a certain strain
of cognitive poetics which seeks quick and comfortable reconciliation with
other, more established, schools of theory (like deconstruction). (I don’t rule
out reconciliation and integration between apparently contradictory or
incommensurate theories – rather I agree with Carroll that one cannot simply
declare peaceful co-existence at the outset.) But in doing so, Carroll puts all
his money on evolution as a new “grand theory,” albeit the right one.
Carroll couldn’t be more explicit about this. The trouble, of course, is that
history is littered with the corpses of similarly righteous (and sincere)
advocates of this or that True Theory of Everything. Carroll refers in passing
to Frederick Crews’ parody of evolutionary literary criticism, but without
acknowledging the principled skepticism of Grand Theory as such underpinning
Crews’ various writings. Is there a danger that Darwinism will come to serve as
still another “intellectual narcotic,” to use Crews’ phrase (Skeptical xi),
a dogma blinding us to the complexities of literature? Within film studies
there has been special attention to this problem, not least among those most
sympathetic to analysis informed by evolutionary and cognitive principles, who
have argued for “middle-level” research and “piecemeal” theorizing in place of
grand theorization (Bordwell,
N. Carroll).
The two problems with “grand theory” that I
want to focus on briefly here are what I’ll call the problem of relevance
and the problem of dependence. The problem of relevance takes us back to
Carroll’s tripartite model of analysis – evolved universal attributes,
culturally-specific instantiations of these attributes, and variations at the
level of the individual – but now with a worry attached. What do we learn when
we set a literary work against the backdrop of “ultimate” evolutionary
explanations, as distinct from more proximate explanatory factors ? How
informative is the level at which we identify the evolved universals at work
within a text ? Gregory Currie worries that “evolution can be of aesthetic
relevance only to the biggest of big pictures,” and that with respect to the
understanding of particular works, it “looks like a blunt instrument” (Currie,
242). The related problem of dependence also bears upon the relations between
ultimate and more proximate levels of analysis. If we forge our proximate
explanations in a fashion such that they are neutral or agnostic with respect
to larger and more distant questions, we insulate them from a problematic
dependence on a particular account of the ultimate factors. If we tie our
proximate explanations closely to a particular ultimate explanation and that
explanation falls, the proximate explanations will go with them.
Consider the 2008 winner of the Oscar for
Best Foreign Film, The Counterfeiters, which tells the story of a group
of (mostly) Jewish concentration camp inmates working on the large-scale
counterfeiting of British and US currency, a strategy devised by the Nazis to
undermine the Allied economies. Even in this most emotionally-charged and
politicized of contexts, we can identify a range of evolved, universal factors which
fundamentally structure the dramatic situation. Much of the film is concerned
with the will to survive in the most invidious circumstances, and with
the psychological and social tactics necessary for a chance of survival in
them. The drama is played out in terms of social dominance and affiliation –
leadership, followship, imprisonment, in-out group dynamics – both between the
Nazi authorities and the prisoners, and within the community of prisoners,
whose unity is under pressure continuously from the tensions between individual
and collective interests, short- and long-term gains, and the interests of
different prisoner groupings emerging from differential treatment by the Nazis.
The entire drama might be understood as a complex elaboration of the kinds of
scenario explored in game theory, like the Prisoner’s Dilemma. Unlike such
models, however, the film dwells on the psychological and emotional costs of
survival under such conditions, focussing on the dilemma faced by its central
protagonist as he is forced to choose between between individual, short-term
survival, and long-term goals and underlying commitments.
Thus far, though, the fact that the film is
a story based on a particular strand of the history of World War II and the
concentration camps, plays no essential role in the analysis. At the universal
level, the story as I’ve described it shares much with Brett Cooke’s analysis
of the dystopian fiction We, alluded to by Carroll. The
Counterfeiters might be understood along similar lines as a fable about the
depersonalizing effects arising from the deprival of basic, evolved human
needs, psychological as well as physical. A more complete and satisfying
understanding of the film thus necessitates attention to the level of cultural
and historical specificity, concerning (most obviously) Nazi ideology, policy
and practice. It also requires attention to the level of the individual work –
considering, for example, the distinctiveness of this story as a story about
the Holocaust, and the particular style and tone of the film’s depiction of the
death camps. The “grand theory” worry, as stated in the problem of relevance,
is that it is only really at the levels of cultural and individual specificity
that the truly informative explanations are forged.[51] A
level of analysis so abstract and “ultimate” that it cannot distinguish between
an anti-communist dystopian fable and a Holocaust drama based on historical
fact must indeed be a “blunt” instrument.
If I’ve understood this line of thinking
correctly, it is not convincing, and Carroll’s multi-level model of literary
analysis stands. Why so ? It is hard to see how incorporating the universal
level of analysis in any way damages the cultural and individual levels, even
if it constrains them by limning the universal “pressure points” underpinning
the drama. The three levels certainly aren’t mutually exclusive, logically
speaking. Nor need attention to the universal level distract us from the
importance of the cultural and individual levels; criticism is not a zero-sum
game. Indeed attention to the universal alongside the cultural and the
individual surely enriches these more specific layers of analysis. The “common
frame of reference” provided by evolutionary theory enables us to appreciate
more sharply the distinct solutions to universal problems generated by
particular cultural traditions, and individual agents (like artists and
authors) working within them (Smith).
The identification of recurrent, “broad and deep” motifs in literary form
across cultures and history provides a plausible explanation for the common
cross-cultural appeal of works of art and literature, which frequently escape
the bounds of the particular cultural tradition in which they were created
(Dutton).
Indeed it is notable that, in the West at
least, the “folk psychology” of criticism – everyday talk about films and works
of literature – incorporates reference to many universalistic concepts, like “human
nature” and “basic instinct,” just as much as it depends on culturally-specific
concepts. As Carroll notes, this kind of convergence between the “common
understanding” and the implications of evolutionary theory stands in its favour
relative to other theories. Finally, in relation to Crews’s concerns about the
dogmatic and “self-validating” (Skeptical xi) tendency of theory as
such, it is important to note that Carroll argues for two distinct, if
overlapping, programs in literary studies: the evolutionary project, and the
empirical project. Bringing the ethos and methods of the empirical sciences into
the study of literature need not be tied to any particular evolutionary theory,
or even evolutionary theory at all. Where evolutionary theory is brought into
play, however, it too is and must be subject to empirical scrutiny: note
Carroll’s exposition of the debate around “massive modularity” within
evolutionary psychology, as an instance of this kind of empirically-driven
revision. So long as evo-lit, along with evolutionary theory more generally,
can maintain this “open” and self-questioning character, there is hope that it
will not turn into just another Theory of Everything heading for the trashcan
of history.
Two other worries are worth briefly noting.
First, Carroll’s overview of literary Darwinism appears to be wholly organized
around and driven by the interventions of evolutionary psychology. Carroll
underlines the centrality of psychology to the evo-lit research program, and
makes it plain that such psychology is genetically-mediated. There is at least
one other branch of evolutionary theory, however, which deserves a hearing in
the context of literary and art theory – the branch that concerns itself with
cultural evolution, that is, with the variation and selection of ideas and
practices within the sphere of culture. In contemporary debate, this question
has mostly been debated under the banner of “memetics” – Richard Dawkins
uncannily catchy name for a cultural equivalent to genetics, the term itself
embodying the idea of an idea which spreads rapidly because of its fitness
within a given cultural environment, in this case the environment of
intellectual debate around evolution. The term itself is controversial, but we
shouldn’t allow that to blind us to the highly plausible notion that there is a
dimension of cultural change at the “population-level,” where patterns of
change emerge from the aggregated choices of individuals, but without the
goal-directedness of individual actions (see also Whiten). Such
supraindividual, population-level patterns are thus “blind” in a manner
parallel to the operations of natural selection. Individual psychology is still
part of the picture here, but not in the way envisaged by evolutionary
psychology.
The second concern bears upon the adaptive
function of literature that Carroll distills from his own work and other evolutionary
theorists like Wilson: literature functions to regulate the potential chaos
arising from human intelligence and the overcoming of purely instinctive
behaviour, furnishing “an emotionally meaningful cognitive map [which] provides
points of reference within which humans adjust their sense of relative value
and the significance of things.”This is an appealing formulation, proferring a
plausible characterization of a “species-typical” evolutionary problem in terms
that traditional humanists will recognize as their own – emotion, value,
significance. Evolutionary theory and traditional literary enquiry appear to
speak to one another on equal terms here. But I wonder if this definition
encompasses too much, or rather more than Carroll has in mind. Doesn’t ideology
perform this function too ? Indeed, don’t all cultural phenomena serve this
orientational and motivational function to some degree ? A Coors beer ad
orients towards certain values and steers us motivationally as much as Middlemarch
(indeed, the relative simplicity and directness of the ad may make it more
effective with respect to this orientational function). Carroll’s account of
the adaptive function of literature may point towards a surprising convergence
with cultural studies, which delights in the levelling of cultural
distinctions.
If these questions do hit upon a raw nerve,
there may be more than one available response to them. Perhaps the adaptive
function of literature – if such there is – needs to be recast to give more
prominence to play and creativity (as in Brain Boyd’s evolutionary account of
fiction, cited by Carroll). Or perhaps, at the level of adaptive function,
literature, propaganda and other overtly ideological tools do form a natural
kind. This wouldn’t stop us from making a principled distinction between
literature and ideology; but it would prevent us from founding that distinction
on the rock of adaptive function. Pinker may be right that much of what we
value has emerged as a by-product rather than as a direct adaptation, but wrong
to imply that this strips such phenomena of their value. The road from “is” to “ought”
is never that direct.
Response to Joseph Carroll’s An
Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Study
Ellen Spolsky, Bar-Ilan University
I am confused about Joseph Carroll’s “we.”
Citing his own earlier work, Carroll notes that he once admitted that “we do not yet have a full and adequate conception of human
nature.” This we may be no more than a variation of
“one”—anyone. But then we hear that, time having passed, Carroll himself is now
able to “lay out a model of human nature that incorporates the features on
which most practitioners in the field would agree.” He does this in 1600 words.
Does he consider himself one of the community of “practitioners?” Or are they
the community of scientists and social scientists who are trained in those
fields? If the second, and that seems more likely, by what authority does he
asks us to accept as accurate or useful his summary of a field that is neither
his nor ours? Beyond my general ability to follow rational argument, how can I
evaluate the claims made therein? The most surprising is the claim that he
reports finding a “consensus” model. Am I being asked to believe that although
my own academic area of literary theory is cross-hatched by contested claims,
the field of evolution and evolutionary psychology is blissfully free of
conflict and competition? Especially when it comes to a model (of all things!)
of human nature? I am being asked to believe in Tinkerbell.
Speaking as one who is quite interested in
the scientific fields of evolutionary biology and cognitive science, I must
protest that it is entirely unreasonable for literary scholars to be asked to
build their own work on a homogenized summary of a field they are not trained
to critique, in which they are not trained to recognize overgeneralizations
from data, to spot weak or faulty research assumptions, to notice the lack of
or poorly defined control groups, or the misplaced use of statistical models.
It is, indeed, ridiculous for literary scholars to include themselves within
the “we” who now “have a model of human nature,” since, as even an amateur
reading of the weekly New York Times science page repeatedly
demonstrates, claims about the universals of human nature remain well beyond
consensus.
While I leave it to others to point out how
much of Carroll’s “model” consists of unproved, even unprovable hypotheses,
most still actively in dispute, Carroll knows perfectly well that his summary
is inadequate for any purpose beyond piquing the interest of the uninformed. He
acknowledges this by providing an example of a “professional” use of these
scientific fields for the study of literature, the work of Brian Boyd, whom he
praises for “expertise in assimilating information from the social sciences;”
Boyd, we are meant to understand, does his homework. With “explicit and
detailed reference to evolutionary social science, Boyd demonstrates that the
findings of cognitive psychology make sense ultimately because they are embedded
in the findings of evolutionary psychology.” To be professional, on this view,
is to “assimilate” (which I take to mean accept and adopt) the claims of two fields in which you are not
trained to be a critical reader! And Carroll hasn’t even had time to mention
the exciting developments in systems biology, clearly relevant as a third field
underpinning whatever ultimately emerges as a description of human nature, but
also a field in which competing hypotheses are vigorously argued.
I was about to submit, then, as my first
complaint, that Carroll is asking us to adopt as guiding principles his
versions of what two or three scientific fields are about, ignoring the quite
reasonable and normal controversy within them about both basic principles and
about details. We must do this, I infer, even though we as literary scholars
have none of the training that would be needed for us to make properly critical
use of their conclusions, because this is the way we will be able to generate
“new” knowledge about literature. I am stopped from advancing this criticism,
however, because just as he asks us to make this commitment, Carroll notes that
there is “one crucial element of human nature [that] remains at least partially
outside this consensus model and that is “the disposition for producing and
consuming literature and the other arts.” Within evolutionary social science,
divergent hypotheses have been formulated about the adaptive function of the
arts.” The good news here is that apparently when it comes to a part of social
science that Carroll actually knows something about from his own professional
training in literature, he does notice a fissure. And if he can notice an area
of controversy here, I ask, shouldn’t he be a bit more suspicious about the
consensus he supposes to exist in the rest of the field? Carroll at this point
seems almost on the verge of realizing that while he cannot advance that theory
as an evolutionary psychologist or biologist, he himself is in possession of a
vast amount of knowledge that the social scientists themselves are in no
position to evaluate or use. He fails, however, to take this next step – to
follow his own evidence. I would like, then, to amplify the intimation he
provides and claim that the position of an outsider to a field, a position we
literary scholars inhabit in respect to evolutionary biology and psychology, is
in fact a fine place from which to make a contribution to the clarification of
the issue or nexus of issues we may label as human nature, a subject in which
many different fields have an interest, and none, I would add, a proprietary
interest. Questions such as the putative adaptive function of the arts are not
going to be answered only by questionnaires and statistics. We can, however,
(and note the different we)
bring our own expertise to the discussion of the hard question of the function
of fiction and of apparently “useless” art work.
My revised complaint, then, is that Carroll
has positioned himself, and asks us to join him, in a situation where he
doesn’t belong—where he has no choice but to listen and to “assimilate,” and
has only a weak and derivative power to critique. Why would we want to do this
when we can bring to the discussion of the function of creative work our
knowledge of a large range of texts stretching over many centuries of human
creativity in many different cultural settings, and our own well-honed
sensitivity to those texts? And in so doing, make our own contribution to the
ongoing project of describing human nature through the study of literary texts
and their functions. Indeed, Carroll does mention some of the projects already
underway in this direction by literary scholars, but seems to measure them
against the hypotheses of the sociobiologist, E.O. Wilson.
Why again, the scientism? As scholars trained to read texts and study
them in their flowering or evanescent cultural contexts, we have evidence that
the scientists don’t know about and wouldn’t be able to learn much from if they
did. We have centuries of evidence about human relationships and motivation,
about economic, or motherly or mating behavior. We have been trained in
theoretical thinking about artwork and in historical methodologies that can
make an enormous contribution to the interdisciplinary project which the study
of human nature surely is. We already have very satisfying ways of studying the
artifacts of art and literature, of philosophy and history so as to advance the
understanding of the relationship of individuals to their world. Why, then,
shouldn’t we continue to do what we are already doing, as many of us in
cognitive literary theory are doing, and that is using our own ways of
understanding of our texts to challenge, refine, and to call attention to some
of the oversimplifications produced by evolutionary and social science. The new
perspective is provided by the questions posed by a Darwinian way of thinking,
but not by any consensus of axioms, since that barely exists.
One of the crucial things we know as
literary scholars is the price the social sciences pay for the reduction away
from the unusual or rare occurrences in human life. In his desire to be
accepted as a practitioner (indeed as the founder) of the new social science of
evolutionary literary theory, Carroll’s production of a story about human
nature fudges its crucial instabilities and gradience just when it gets
interesting to us in the literature departments. On the description of human
nature he provides, “human nature’ is understood as something like a collection
of “genetically mediated characteristics typical of the human species.” He
expands on the next page: “Evolution has shaped the anatomical, physiological,
and neurological characteristics of the species, and …human behavior, feeling,
and thought [so that they are] fundamentally constrained and informed by those
characteristics.” Here again, Carroll fails to notice important hints in his
own discourse – here the important modifiers buried in the word “typical” and
in the word “constraints.” These words indicate general but not absolute
control, and it is just here that a deep and wide familiarity with literary
texts and other art forms is going to be the most useful in enriching the
description of human nature. From where we stand as literary scholars, we
should be working to argue and to demonstrate that the full project of
understanding human nature is not going to succeed without an understanding of
exceptionality. It is only through an account of the occasional, the unusual
and the non-typical that change can be understood. It is somewhat ironic, then,
that this hypothesis, so important to those of us who may spend years studying
one text, is also central to evolutionary theory. Instead of arguing that we
(all of us) are still constrained by the genetic limits that structured our
existence on the Pleistocene savannah, some social scientists have already
begun to work out the mechanics of co-evolution. They are beginning to find
evidence about how culture interacts with biology to produce not only cultural
but even genetic change.
It seems clear that an understanding of the
exceptions which literature regularly describes—the “tellable” to use Mary
Louise Pratt’s word for those occurrences in which literature and art are
focally interested – is what is needed for the interdisciplinary project of
literature and cognitive science. It is, in fact, ludicrous to think that in
the project of describing human nature, the novels of Jane Austen are needed to
confirm the understanding that mating is crucial for the continuation of the
species! Instead of rewriting our knowledge so that social scientists will find
it comfortable – tabulating, for example, the percentages of male and female
characters in folktales – we may ask, for example, what can be learn about
gender and mating from the dyad of Puccini’s Madame Butterfly (Milan, 1904) and the American playwright,
David Henry Hwang’s award winning drama of 1988, M. Butterfly? It is unfortunate that Carroll encourages
projects he calls literary, but which seem aimed at turning our knowledge into
their kind of knowledge instead of using our knowledge to discuss mutually
interesting questions.
Ultimately what Wilson called
consilience is not going to be achieved by importing the methods appropriate to
the laboratory or even to social science inquiry into the humanities.
Consilience is more likely to come from a general recognition that there are
different kinds of reduction—different methodologies that need to find out how
to appreciate each other’s insights. It’s not consilience when I distort my
subject matter so that it fits someone else’s analytical instruments. If “we”
are going to be one community, we need to learn how to use each others’ deepest
understanding by working in multiple directions at once.
Carroll
continues to show his superb mastery of the field here, and I can add little to
his summary of the accomplishments, struggles, and schisms that mark that
field’s progress. Where I might hang a footnote is to his response to that
“crucial element of human nature” that “remains at least partially outside
[the] consensus model: the disposition for producing and consuming literature
and the other arts.” Like Carroll, I believe that all the arts have adaptive
value; in fact, I would go farther and affirm with Ellen Dissanayake that the
arts give evidence in human beings for a “biologically endowed adaptive
behavioral proclivity” (“’Making’” 27). I am in complete agreement with
Carroll’s objections to Pinker’s relegation of the arts to pleasure-machines,
as well as to Miller’s characterization of them as “useless ornaments.” His
defense is quite strong. But I am uneasy with Carroll’s own alternative
hypothesis, at least as regards literature, the art that is at the focus of the
essay. Here is Carroll’s explanation:
The adaptive value of high intelligence is
that it provides the means for behavioral flexibility, for dealing with
contingent circumstances and hypothetical situations. That behavioral
flexibility has made of the human species the most successful alpha predator of
all time, but achieving dominance in this way has come with a cost. [E.O.]
Wilson speaks of the “psychological exile” of the species. . . . The
proliferation of possibilities in “mental scenarios” detached from instinct
produces a potential chaos in organizing motives and regulating behavior and
the elemental passions that derive from human life history. The arts are thus
an adaptive response to the adaptive problem produced by theadaptive capacities
of high intelligence.
The human being of “high intelligence” is
no longer a creature of “instinct,” true, but I would argue that it is not
necessarily prey to “chaos” in its organizing and regulating skills, however
numerous the “mental scenarios” it entertains. The “motives,” “behavior,” and
“passions” that Carroll is referring to belong presumably to the human social
world (“human life history”), and, for that world, the creature without
instincts has evolved a finely tuned system of emotions. That system is
more than adequate to the demands of social scenarios of both the immediate
moment and the far-flung future, and it makes stabilizingly good sense of the
events of both the near and the distant past (if we give, of course, some
allowance to the ways egotism always skews the results!). With Wilson, I agree
that our species is psychologically exiled, but not, I think, from its once
instinctively managed social skills. The nature of that exile will be addressed
later in this response.
A
second point of divergence between Carroll and me is the definition of art,
specifically, here, of literary art. I agree strongly that to solve “the puzzle
of adaptive function,” we must first “define art in a way that identifies what
is peculiar and essential to it.” But I have difficulty in descrying a
definition of Carroll’s own in his essay. The closest we seem to come to it is
in the remarks that Carroll quotes from the book he has co-authored with
Johnson and Kruger: “Literature and its oral antecedents derive from a uniquely
human, species-typical disposition for producing and consuming imaginative verbal
constructs.” The phrase “imaginative verbal constructs” can embrace much that
is not art, of course: Gossip is often quite imaginative, but it is also often
rambling, shapeless, tediously tendentious, and dull. We need, to set the
stage, a sharper definition of art and a convincing account of the adaptive
function that is unique to it.
I
have found a no more compelling definition than that of Ellen Dissanayake, who
has given it elaboration in three books and dozens of articles over the last
twenty years or so. Art, she insists, should be linked not exclusively to
artifacts but to a specific kind of behavior. That behavior she calls
“making-special.”
Each
of the arts can be viewed as ordinary behavior made special (or
extra-ordinary). This is easy to see in dance, poetry, and song. In dance,
ordinary bodily movements of everyday life are exaggerated, patterned,
embellished, repeated—made special. In poetry, the usual syntactic and semantic
aspects of everyday spoken language are patterned (by means of rhythmic meter,
rhyme, alliteration, and assonance), inverted, exaggerated (using special
vocabulary and unusual metaphorical analogies), and repeated (e.g., in
refrains)—made special. In song, the prosodic (intonational and emotional)
aspects of everyday language—the ups and downs of pitch, pauses or rests,
stresses or accents, crescendos and diminuendos of dynamics, accelerandos and
rallentandos of tempo—are exaggerated (lengthened and otherwise emphasized),
patterned, repeated, varied, and so forth—made special. In the visual arts,
ordinary objects like the human body, the natural surroundings, and common
artifacts are made special by cultural shaping and elaboration to make them
more than ordinary. (“’Making’” 30-31)
Carroll has expressed reservations about
such a definition, pointing out that prisoners’ striped uniforms are “special”
garments but cannot be regarded as art (pers. comm.). But the example seems to
me weak: The stripes in question are not an elaboration upon the uniform but a
simple code, like a traffic sign: “Prisoner Inside.” Dissanayake herself has
conceded that both play and ritual are not excluded by the definition, but I
think that our instincts rebel in admitting at least the first of those
behaviors into the realm of art. As the early evolutionary aesthetician Felix
Clay remarked: “No doubt there is a superficial resemblance between some of the
forms of art and play; one important difference that we must note is that every
manifestation of art produces something—the essence of it involves the
alteration of matter in the creation of new forms [either in the concrete or,
as with pantomime or dance, in the cultural memory]” (31). And, as for ritual,
Dissanayake has in her latest book brought it comfortably within the fold:
“’Ceremony,’” she writes, is “a one-word term for what is really a collection
or assembly of elaborations (of words, voices, actions, movements, bodies,
surroundings, and paraphernalia)—that is, of arts (chant or song, poetic
language, ordered movement and gesture or dance, mime, and drama, along with
considered and even spectacular visual display)” (Art 138).
But
why does the human being “make special”? What adaptive function does such a
behavior have? The usual answer is that, in its ceremonial form, it ensures
group cohesiveness; in Dissanayake’s words, it promotes “communality and
one-heartedness” (“Making” 33). But I suspect that cohesiveness is a
spin-off—albeit an extremely valuable one—from the original function of the
arts. To get at that function, we should reinsert the arts into the lives of
their earliest creators. Steven Pinker thinks that, to understand art, “We need
to begin with . . . paintings on black velvet” (How 523). But that is
not where our ancestors began. They began apparently with displays associated with
shock and pain and intensively deliberative labor—at least so the artifactual
evidence indicates. (We have no way of knowing when dancing and chanting and
singing and drumming evolved—or what exactly they were like at their
inception.) The manipulation of red ochre (presumably to paint the body),
cranial deformation, filed or ablated teeth, beads manufactured as ornaments:
these are among the earliest surviving testimonials of human “making-special.”
Each changed the reassuringly familiar human image in jarring, even grotesque
ways, sometimes (as in the sharpening of teeth, still performed by some
present-day tribal groups—with machetes) at the cost of great pain and precious
time. (White notes that “Experiments conducted with elephant ivory at New York
University [NYU], using faithful replicas of Aurignacian tool-forms, suggest an
average time per basket-shaped bead of well in excess of an hour” [554].) Art
for the peoples of the early Upper Paleolithic had nothing to do with
bare-breasted señoritas couched coyly against backgrounds of black velvet:
Their art, as the anthropologist David Stout has argued about the art of modern
“primitives,” was intended, not to push the “pleasure buttons” (Pinker, How
525), but most probably to evoke awe. Early art, I suggest, as
Dissanayake does (Art 131), was inseparable from early religion; the two
seem to have co-evolved. Art, in its “specialness,” served religion as a bridge
to the sacred world.
This
last point deserves considerable elaboration, not something that I have very
much space for, so I must beg indulgence from the reader for my sketchiness.
The chief proponents, among anthropologists, for the theory that religion
evolved as an “adaptive complex” are Candace S. Alcorta and Richard Sosis, who
argue that religion emerged in response to “increased competition between
groups for patchy resources” (347): “Religious symbols . . . provided tools for
creating cooperative coalitions across time” (348). In other words, religion
evolved—as so many others before them have argued—“to differentiate and
cohesify [human] groups” (348). But this explanation does not satisfy me. The
purely material problem that they describe could easily have been met by a
purely material solution. Why is it assumed that religion, and not, say,
well-armed conscripts of zealous thugs, was best suited to “differentiate and
cohesify human groups”? My own theory is that religion evolved to solve a metaphysical
problem, one that could not have been solved in any other way. When Wilson
speaks of the “psychological exile” of the species, he describes that exile in
specific terms: “The great apes have the power of self-recognition, but there
is no evidence that they can reflect on their own birth and eventual death”
(245). I think it was the latter of those two mysteries that excited the most
reflection (because it excited the most fear and anguish) among our early
art-making ancestors. Religion was their response to that mystery, and the arts
were the tools for gaining public access to its “special” deathless realm and,
in the process, uniting initiates in their faith and thereby strengthening them
in their convictions.
That
religion was born of the consciousness of every individual’s inevitable death
is argued most persuasively by Conrad Montell, who concedes that his position
is “highly speculative” (1). But, for all its speculativeness, it addresses the
problem of the emergence of religion with fiercely compelling force. How
confront or escape a predator—death—that, unlike every other predator, cannot
apparently be defeated? And how live in the world in psychological
comfort—which is to say, with robust inclusive fitness—with the daily knowledge
of one’s own inevitable defeat?
What
“tools” might be found or made to “reshape” death? Those who had the ability to
think such questions were on their way to answers. Early humans who developed
rituals to mourn the dead, and then developed magic or religion to make the
apprehension of death “bearable,” would function
better: would tend to be less debilitated by fear of death, as individuals and
in community. (Montell 17)
Such humans used the newly acquired faculty
of reflection (“imagination,” in Montell’s terminology) to amass redemptive
evidence of a world beyond this material one and so beyond the jaws of death.
In dreams, in drug- or trance- or dance-induced transports and hallucinations,
and even in psychotic episodes (as when the schizophrenic is guided by
“voices”), early reflective humanity undoubtedly found much that was suggestive
of such a world. But only through art, deployed in ritual, could public
access to that world be established and assured. Art was “special” to our early
ancestors not only in sensory but also, more importantly, in ontological terms.
Like holy water, which both is and is not H2O, the artfully
elaborated object, movement, or sound served as a portal between this world and
the noumenal Other. And still does so for many today: “In the quasi-spiritual
connotations of capital-A art,” writes Dissanayake, “it is as if there is a
sort of archetypal memory of what the arts [once] did for us” (What
168). (In defense of which I quote the capital-A abstractionist Mark Rothko:
“The people who weep before my pictures,” he once told an interviewer, “are
having the same religious experience I had when I painted them” [May 119].)
And
that experience produced—and still produces—enormous benefits. “Cohesiveness”
is the most obvious of those benefits: Religion unites all its believers
through its ideology and its ritual, and in their union is their strength. A
growing body of research also indicates that individual believers, as could be
expected, are better equipped physically in the “struggle for existence” than
are those for whom death still bears a sting: “These studies,” write Alcorta
and Sosis, “demonstrate decreased mental and physical health risks, faster
recovery times for a wide variety of disorders, and greater longevity for those
who regularly attend weekly Western religious services, even when social and
lifestyle confounds are controlled (Hummer et al. 1999; Matthews et al. 1998;
Murphy et al. 2000)” (324). And when the behaviors that were born of the
religious impulse—the “making-special” that defines the arts—are visited upon
unmistakably profane social scenarios, as in narrative, the artful and
articulate acquire a powerful tool. Geoffrey Miller disagrees: “The best
commands,” he writes in The Mating Mind, “are imperative sentences, not
works of art” (263). In response, I direct the reader to a recent Jane Smiley
novel, in which a character asks his lover if she has ever been to an AA
meeting:
“What
they do at meetings is tell stories. You aren’t allowed to give advice or tell
people what to do. You’re encouraged to tell your own story and leave it at
that. The reason they do that is because alcoholics can be volatile and
sometimes take offense. Telling stories is the least offensive way to
communicate because it’s the least coercive. . . .” (235, my italics)
And when a non-coercive behavior, like
story-telling, is “made special” by a master, it acquires the authority and
persuasiveness of all successful art. Artful narratives, as Brian Boyd
observes, “command and consecrate shared attention” (“The Origin” 204,
my italics). They carry the rapt listener out of the gossipy profane and into the
imaginatively sacred. And, in doing so, they construct whole lives and
cultures. Merlin Donald is the most eloquent on this theme:
Western
religion, through its domination of the mythic resources of Europe, was able to
influence every date on the calendar, every major architectural and engineering
project, every library, and every philosophical and literary work.. . .
Similarly, the Crusades were fought, and new continents conquered, largely
because of an idea fixed in a narrative framework of what the world was like or
should be like. Stories of imaginary places, like the kingdom of Prester John,
or of the coming of the Apocalypse have inspired people to give up their roots
to live in danger and often to die. (296)
“We are dominated by our stories,” writes Donald: “They not only can
spell out the project of a life but can provide a sense of group identification
that drives people to attempt almost anything” (295, 296). And when
“consecrated” by art, they achieve transcendent power. It was through art’s awesomeness
that early humanity found succor in its exile from innocence. “We like the
world because we do,” wrote Wallace Stevens (913). I propose that we like it
because art, as the handmaid of religion, redeemed it for us from death.
Some disciplines are fortunate to find
expositors who are as erudite as eloquent. Evolution had its Darwin,
behaviourist psychology had Skinner, transformational linguistics had
Chomsky—and Darwinian literary studies has Joseph Carroll. For almost two
decades, he has done as much as anyone else to bring the discipline into being,
then into focus, and “An Evolutionary Paradigm for Literary Study” is but the
latest effort to forge a consilient paradigm of literary study. In the spirit and
the letter of the essay, let me briefly comment on several research avenues for
literary study it touches on.
1. The Turing Test
“Underlying this inquiry is the assumption that the evolution of
computing machines will lead to the point when they become able spontaneously
to create works of literature” (93).
Peter Swirski, Between Literature and Science
In the version of evolutionary psychology that lies behind Steven
Pinker’s view of the arts, writes Carroll, “the governing conception of the
mind is computational, and the governing metaphor for the mind is that of the
computer”. Significantly, up until very recently the AI optimists were still
reluctant to concede the defeat of the top-down (GOFAI) approach that spoon-fed
computers information which, at some point, was supposed to jump-start
independent thinking. Now we know it is a dead-end. A thinking computer will
not be built: it will build itself by modifying its rulebook, erasing some
pre-loaded instructions, adding new ones, and turning itself effectively into
an intentional black box. In one word, it will evolve.
Generally speaking,
survival-oriented behaviour comes in two flavours (in actuality it is hard to
find them in isolation). The first is the genotypal homeostat whose hard-wired instinct guarantee a swift response to standard
environmental stimuli. The second is the phenotypal homeostat that
learns—organizes behaviour on the basis of historically acquired knowledge.
Learning is an organism's ability to acquire information and feed it back into
its behaviour, including notably the learning process itself. The chronic
absence of success in programming general problem-solving heuristics indicates
that progress in that domain will come when computers will learn to learn. A
learning machine will able to rewrite its program in the course of its
operations, ultimately changing its configuration to the point where it may no longer
be the original machine but a new, independently thinking one.
There are principled ways of
investigating whether computers can (be said to) think, and by far the most
famous and controversial among them is the Turing test (TT). Most arguments
about the evolution of thinking in computers end up being arguments about the
validity and extension of the TT. Significantly, from the point of view of
literary theorists, the heart of the matter is the subject’s verbal
performance during the TT, which warrants analysis in linguistic,
narratological, rhetorical, and cognate terms. Even more significantly from the
point of view of literary evolutionary theorists, the variety of
pragmatic Mutual Contextual Beliefs in this context implies the need to
formulate a Theory of Mind by the examiner—or, in the upgrade of the test I
proposed in Between Literature and Science—by the computer itself.
Research in literary studies might make a contribution to the analysis of this
dimension of evolving, thinking, and ultimately literature-creating
(third-order) computers.
2. Game Theory
“Before drawing the two matrixes for the Mission Game, I must encourage
readers to resist the feeling that this sort of analysis may be too arcane for
them to understand.” (142)
Peter Swirski, Of Literature and Knowledge
Evolution and game theory fuse directly in
evolutionary game theory. Insofar as it makes little sense to treat animals as
rational decision-makers, evolutionary game theory treats environmentally
stable outcomes as survival strategies sustained by evolution, whereby the
payoffs for animal populations are assumed to reflect their degree of environmental
fitness. In a notable reversal, of late evolutionary game
theory has become of interest to social scientists. Game theoretic calculus
can, as it turns out, be usefully applied to dynamic systems such as
cultural formations, and the rationality assumptions of dynamic fitness are
frequently better suited to reflect the iterative interactions of social
systems.
Although matrix analysis is
an effective tool to analyze multiplex decision nodes, it
is by no means a universal panacea for literary scholars. For one, it offers no
reprieve from textual indeterminacy inherent in fiction. Even more important,
identification of conflicts and players, enumeration of their strategic
choices, and the (cardinal or merely ordinal) ranking of outcomes, can also be
contentious. But this is where game theory comes into its own. Formally
foregrounding its analytic assumptions, it invites alternative interpretations
of events by offering an exact methodology to study personal—as well as
interpersonal—aspects of character and plot. It makes
explicit the psychological motivations and utilities of narrative agents, and
when possible, offer a solution to the game in question.
Given that most narratives are amenable to exploration along
these lines, game theory can illuminate narrative conflicts as diverse as the
beheading game in Sir Gawain, the tit-for-tat tug-of-war between Chaucer’s
Miller and Reeve, Jane Austen’s parlour love “games”, and the strategic nuance
of espionage games in Graham Greene. Indeed, this universality prompts Carroll
to remark that the game theoretic framework may be useful “as a thematic
filter for summarizing character interaction in a wide variety of literary
works.” Most novels, after all,
introduce complex characters and motivations, and most novelists intuitively employ game-theoretic principles
to the extent that such principles are part of all human beings’ innate
psychological equipment. In that sense, bringing those tacit procedures to the
surface in the form of an explicit analytic framework can provide literary
theorists with better access to the deep structures of human behavioural
economy.
3. Thought Experiments
“The basic premise behind Of Literature
and Knowledge is that the capacity of literary fictions for generating
nonfictional knowledge owes to their capacity for doing what philosophy and
science do—generating thought experiments” (4).
Peter Swirski, Of Literature and
Knowledge
Carroll draws
attention to our capacity for thought experimenting by “contrasting
instinct with the human capacity for considering counterfactual and
hypothetical circumstances”. Counterfactual reasoning
confers a distinct adaptive advantage inasmuch as it is a cheap and efficient
way of dealing with an infinity of historical alternatives and future
possibilities. The payoffs are fantastic in any environment whose instability
exceeds the pace of natural selection to hard-wire organisms for behavioural
contingencies. The Homo who could work out the decision nodes in their
head, instead of slogging down every forking and beast-ridden path, greatly
bettered his odds of making it to the mating season.
In the
twilight of the nineteenth century, William James’s Principles of Psychology
envisioned the mind as an all-purpose generator and selector of ideas best
suited to deal with the world. In the twilight of the twentieth, E.O. Wilson’s Consilience
fleshed out such adaptive faculties in terms of a prodigious library of
scenarios. Not to be confused with Hollywood scripts, this technical term
denotes mental coding networks—motion-picture engrams, if you like—that,
processed in massive parallel, yield the decisions that we make in life. Like
everywhere else, variation and fierce selection determine the degree of fit to
the environment in question. Supporting a limitless array of responses,
literary scenarios are a species of cognitive truck with the world.
The cognitive
component should not be understood literally as a context-specific database of
action scenarios but rather a contingent library of behavioural attitudes, emotions
and dispositions. The fundamental question about its cognitive
proficiency—especially salient in literary fictions, those multipurpose
generators and selectors of “decoupled” ideas—is the dilemma of
informativeness. Where does the knowledge of the real world reside in these
unreal fantasies? What are the cognitive mechanisms that allow fictions
to provide nonfictional knowledge? The narrative analogues to such
cognitive mechanisms sketched in Of Literature and Knowledge are but the
first steps on a road that beckons with a promise of putting literary studies
on firm footing with regard to evolutionary epistemology.
4. Aesthetics
“For the record, no one, not even E.O.
Wilson, has ever claimed that placing literature and literary studies in the
context of empirical science could ever tap the full aesthetic nuance, formal
artistry, or symbolic and interpretive contingency of literary works—the
traditional provenance of literary criticism.”
Peter Swirski, Literature, Aesthetically
Speaking
Insofar, writes Carroll, as evolution is
the ur discipline that unites the hard with the social sciences and the
humanities, literary Darwinists envision “an integrated body of knowledge
extending in an unbroken chain of material causation from the lowest level of
subatomic particles to the highest levels of cultural imagination”. Although one
outspoken critic of such a vision has recently sought to counter the errors and
mystifications allegedly perpetrated by evolutionary scholars, literary and
not, Eugene Goodheart’s critique is a rhetorical legerdemain perpetrated by a
confusion of literary research with aesthetic criticism. Axiological
interpretation is a crucial element of literary-critical—more broadly,
sociocultural—engagement with art. But evaluative criticism and
interdisciplinary research are far from the same enterprise, for
subjective and adventitious readings do not contribute to any cumulative
research paradigm in any consilient sense of the word.
Even
as he vociferates against reductionism in the humanities, Goodheart himself
adopts a dismayingly reductionist, i.e. bipolar view of literary research as a
postmodern skepticism vs hardcore scientism. This caricature—which underpins
his entire critique—could never do justice to the gamut of contemporary literary-critical
responses to cognition and research. And yet, the critic’s warnings against
impoverished translations of research data from one field into another are
worth heeding insofar as they go to the heart of any interdisciplinary research
program. Even in its short history, literary-evolutionary studies has been
prone to cookie-cutter criticism, whereby literature is used mainly as a dough
from which critics cut out just the parts that confirm theories from other
fields. Such scholarship has to be warded off, for art is more than a
compelling illustrator of established socio-biological theories.
Literary
studies may aspire not just to exemplify but complexify research in other
disciplines. Within evolutionary studies, for instance, literary scholars can at
a minimum ensure that the paradigm does not gloss over the adaptive function of
human propensity for art. Literature multiplies models of reality that operate
on the subjective and emotional level, organizing categories of human
experience of the world. That is why, reading stories, we often feel that they
ring true, even as it may not be easy to articulate this feeling in
propositional form. This intuitive, not to say instinctive, determination of
the (folk psychological) truth of the story is precisely what drives research
into literary representations. Our brains and minds are hardwired to avoid
dangers, distinguish friends from foes, spot cheaters or opportunities to
advance our interests—in short, to form a passable picture of the world. And
this behavioural baseline, expressed in the ubiquitous and universal criteria
for representational truth, can furnish literary studies with a “ruler” for
determining the accuracy of narrative models.
This description feeds
the argument that the adaptive function of literature is to create storyworlds
within which we make (dispositional) sense of our own behaviour. Living in the
imagination is a peculiarly human condition, whereby fictional events are
synthesized into imaginative constructs that involve our sense of the
total order of nature and human social relations extending in time. Much
of the time we do not think about those relations in abstractions (a late
part of human cognitive equipment). Instead, readers experience the
complex order of things in narrative fictions supercharged with
emotions. And because they are so charged and extend over time, these
fictions acquire a dramatic character which makes us emote with imaginary
people, which in turn helps us calibrate our own emotions, attitudes and
behaviours—all of which is open not just to aesthetic interpretation, but to
scientific analysis. And as such, I cannot do better than close with words that can serve as an epitaph for
the whole section, article, and discipline:
Science
can explain why and how art has come to matter, but that will not give science
the emotional impact of art, nor allow it to find a formula for art, nor make
art matter less. If anything, it will only clarify why and how art matters so
much (Boyd, “Evolutionary” 172).
Blakey Vermeule
Joseph
Carroll’s writing has been enormously important to me. Everything I say here is
meant with the deepest appreciation for his energy, kindness, intelligence, and
sheer dogged persistence in advancing the cause of literary Darwinism. My remarks are skeptical, but only because I
think appreciating art and explaining it are two somewhat distinct
activities. Darwinian literary study
aims to improve the ways we explain art and to improve the content of our
explanations. I heartily support this effort. I only doubt that it will make
much difference to what English professors do, which is to help people touch
the terrible danger and power of art.
When I started graduate school in 1990, we
were required to take a course in literary methods. Most graduate programs
offer such courses yet their contents are always changing, their syllabi shaped
by the tastes of whoever is in charge.
This would hardly be true in any other discipline--physics, say, or
economics, or musicology. What does this
tell us about literary methods? Years of pondering this question have led me to
conclude that--to put it bluntly--there are no literary methods because
literary study is not a discipline. Its practitioners are not scientists but
members of a secular clerisy drawn to some branch or other of quasi-theological
speculation. To say this is in no way to
impugn my profession. In fact I rather like this state of affairs. I believe deeply in the transformative,
inspirational, soul-shaking power of literature. I am enormously grateful that
universities have, for reasons of their own, given a place to humanists to
explore aesthetic power (even though nobody comes right out and admits that
that’s what we do). In my own intellectual life I am a committed Darwinian and
a rabid anti-mysterian. But I’ve come to believe that literary study is a
branch of human spiritual practice rather than human knowledge--spilt religion,
if you like, rather than spilt science.
All
of this makes the challenge from Joseph Carroll and the literary Darwinians
especially intriguing. Carroll argues that taking a consilient approach to
literary study holds out the hope of progress in the discipline. What does this
challenge mean? Where will it lead? I am desperately rooting for it to succeed
simply out of intellectual loneliness. Theory is responsible for some of the
deep eclecticism of today’s humanities, having become, in its terminal stages,
so unfalsifiable as to leave people with nothing to say to each other. Someone
can make a specious claim, about language or gender, and nobody will to refute
it. Someone else can make another specious claim--and silence again. Pretty
soon everyone is stuck in their own corner muttering to themselves--this is the
university as Borges or Swift might have imagined it. Literary darwinism gives
us a chance to speak with a common language, a language that runs with the
grain of human nature rather than in any old direction. This will certainly
improve the intellectual climate overall:
more interesting conferences, fewer silly statements, less hair-tearing,
less teeth-gnashing (I speak for myself).
So
what are my doubts? Only that having a common, science-based language will make
much difference to what English professors do.
Aesthetic power--the love and appreciation of great art--taps into that
old oceanic feeling. Humanists are tour guides to the ocean’s depths as much
as, and probably more than, we are oceanographers sitting on the surface and
measuring the sea. The most successful
members of our profession are not philosophers or historians but still even at
this late date, critics--people who explain really well what artists are up to
(about which more in a moment). Whether it is practiced on the page or in the
classroom, good criticism is a fiendishly difficult craft. People crave explanations of art, insofar as
they do, because knowing some context dramatically increases the pleasure art
gives us. Just as challenges from
science have not in the least lessened the grip of religious belief on people’s
psyches, so challenges from empiricist humanists are not going to lessen the
grip of aesthetic power. And in the end, reaching towards those fragile works
of mastery and genius is the work we’re called on to do.
Let
me give an analogy. In Richard Dawkins’s documentary on religious faith, The
Root of All Evil, Dawkins travels to Colorado Springs to meet Ted Haggard,
the pastor of the New Life Church, a massive dominionist congregation. (Dawkins
filmed this segment just before Haggard, a husband and father of four children,
was found to be visiting male prostitutes in Denver and buying crystal meth).
In the video, Dawkins buttonholes Haggard and they exchange sharp words.
Dawkins asks Haggard, in effect, how he can mislead his congregation so badly.
Eventually Haggard throws Dawkins and his camera crew off church property and
accuses them of telling his parishioners that they are “apes.” Watching the
clip, all my sympathies lie with Dawkins. But I can’t help thinking that his
scolding rationalism, though fun to watch, simply misses the point. The New
Life congregants haven’t come to church for the theology. If the theology helps
get them in the right frame of mind, so much the better. But really they come
for the emotional pleasure, pleasure that the swirling lights and the loud
music and the us-versus-them rhetoric help to trigger.
Drawing
an analogy between the New Life Church and university humanities departments
may sound nihilistic and mysterian indeed (not to mention suicidal). But to me
the analogy is apt. Theory has taken hold in humanities departments because it
is (or was) a branch of theology, not science. Its explanatory aims are finally
subordinate to its emotive ones: it
gives people energy and the will to do the work. Theory has been more or less overtly driven
by a liberationist agenda—and it has developed strong resemblances to religious
cults, in which powerful gurus dispense dogma and their disciples disseminate
it. Some theory-centered disciplines make this more or less explicit. Take
feminist studies. Feminist studies has
been driven explicitly by a liberationist agenda but it has signally refused to
address—in fact has been entirely contemptuous of—the mounting evidence that
there are significant hormonal, neurological, and cognitive differences between
the sexes. If you can’t admit the question, you aren’t a discipline. Michel Foucault, in other words, was onto
something when he drew his famous distinction between scientific discourses and
discourses that were under the sway of the “author-function.” The latter are
schools of thought in which the founder’s charismatic presence determines what
can be said or thought even many generations later (think Marxism, or
Freudianism, or yes, Foucauldianism).
Many
of the intellectual movements embraced by the humanities have this character,
which should be a clue to their quasi-religious status. So will clearing them
away in favor of science really make a difference to what English departments
do? Here again I am skeptical. Let me go back to that course I took in 1990.
The profession of literary studies was invented, sort of, in the late 19th
century. It was reinvented several times since then, especially forcefully in
the 1920’s, the 1940’s and the 1970’s. In 1990 our literary methods course was
divided into two parts. In the first part we learned some theory. English
professors were still trying to make sense of what had happened in the 1970’s,
so the theory we learned was a rough blend of the ideas of Paul de Man and
Michel Foucault. But the second part of the course had a more practical
character. It consisted of a set of instructions. 1. Pick a well-known text. 2.
Write three papers about it. The papers
had to be in this order: the composition
history; the reception history; a critical crux. To do the last one, we went
to the library and looked up the recent criticism in the giant bound volumes of
the MLA bibliography. Then we picked some issue that people had found
especially puzzling (like, say, why Robinson Crusoe finds only a single
footprint on the sand of his island) and followed its trail back to its origins
in the text. These instructions were quite useful and, as I recall, the papers
I wrote were full of information. Information, facts, and some claims, too.
Claims about what? When you get right down to it, the claims were simple. They
were about what my author had thought he was up to, what he intended, what he
meant.
When
you strip out theory, the question of what an author intended is still, even
now, at the core of the organized and professional study of literature. The
question gets stretched this way and that, pulled on the rack of biography or
mounted on the frame of historical narrative. But once you begin to parse the
more elaborate claims, you realize that they can still be boiled down to
authors and what they intended. Literary critics make claims about writers and
artists, sometimes about the history of genre or the practice of literary
forms. But these claims are usually meant to illuminate texts, writers, aesthetics.
Can
evolutionary theory intersect with literary study at this level? I’m not sure
it can, or if it does, whether the answers will yield anything much in the way
of literary knowledge. Let me give an example. For a long time I’ve been
interested in the South African novelist and Nobel Laureate J.M. Coetzee. One of his more persistent themes has been an
older man’s lust for young women. The story he tells over and over again is of
a man in his middle-middle to older middle age who thinks sexual thoughts about
much younger women, sexual thoughts for which he feels he may be punished. The
old man makes much of his physical decline:
“my thin shanks, my slack genitals, my flabby old man’s breasts, the
turkey skin of my throat” (Waiting for the Barbarians). He makes much of
his sexual impotence, his unattractiveness to women. The younger woman taunts
him with her sexual potency, with her fertility, her availability to other men,
but she withholds herself from him sexually. Why will he be punished for having
sexual thoughts about her? Well he--the Coetzee persona, embodied in various
male characters of his- doesn’t say directly but he leaves some clues. He
thinks it is the condition of men to be punished by women, by feminists
especially, for their desires. All of this is perfectly consilient with
Darwin’s theory of sexual selection, and indeed closely related themes can be
found in the writings of Coetzee’s contemporaries or near
contemporaries--Philip Roth, Saul Bellow, V.S. Naipaul and others. But to explain
why Coetzee chooses this theme, a critic would have to look into the role not
of Darwin in his work nor of sexual selection on his psyche, but of his deep
reverence for Tolstoy and Dostoyevsky, for Becket and Kafka. Coetzee has
philosophical ambitions, ambitions having to do with his belief that reason is
a failed and failing implement. Whether he’s right about this, and whether his
beliefs are ultimately consilient with biology, is not finally the sort of
question a critic gets to ask. At least not if she’s trying to explain the
writings of J.M. Coetzee and not to use his writing as a tool to some other
unrelated ends.
****************************************************************************************************************
[1] See Boyd, “”Artistic,” “Art of Literature,” and On the Origin.
[2] Doidge speaks of “focused attention, the condition for plastic change” in the brain (111).
[3] See Inoue and Matsuzawa.
[4] See Tomasello et al.
[5] See Dissanayake, Art and Intimacy; Goleman; Hobson; and Trevarthen.
[6] See Gordon et al.
[7] See Levitin.
[8] See Richerson and Boyd; and Wilson and Wilson.
[9] See Tomasello et al.
[10] See Burghardt, “Darwin’s Enduring Legacy.”
[11] See also Dissanayake, Homo Aestheticus.
[12] See C. Darwin, The Expression.
[13] See Burghardt, “Instinct.”
[14] See Cooke, “Evolution of Interest.”
[15] See Cooke, “Microplots.”
[16] See Cooke, Human Nature.
[17] See Cooke, “Microplots.”
[18] Carroll generously acknowledged those efforts on my part. At the same time, he asserted, with disapproval, that Crews “is sympathetic to the political orientation of the poststructuralists, and he is disposed to give the strongest possible weight to the positive political motives for their theoretical formulations” (Carroll, Evolution 11). This was a misperception, perhaps deriving from an effort on my part to distinguish my position from that of Roger Kimball, who had objected to egalitarian sentiments per se on the academic left. From 1972 onward, I had repeatedly criticized the merely gestural radicalism of many literary academics (see System and Engagements). As that revolutionism-in-the-head became bundled with Contintental “Theory,” I demurred as forcefully as I could through both argument and satire, and I have continued to do so (see Critics, Postmodern, and Follies).
[19] Crews, Follies 8. See also chapters 14 and 15 of the same book.
[20] Despite the Laplacean air of this last sentence, other passages make it clear that Carroll is no believer in billiard-ball determinism in the cultural realm. By “material causation” he surely means that cultural manifestations result not from empty deductive constructs such as “the Western mind” or “the spirit of the age” but from conjunctions of real-world factors operating on individual persons.
[21] Carroll, “Human Nature” 95.
[22] Carroll, “Human Nature” 100.
[23] There is no unchallenged evidence for a psychic mechanism of repression. (For a recent comprehensive survey of the literature, see Rofé, “Does Repression Exist?”) Why does the scientifically minded Carroll feel entitled to put this threadbare concept to argumentative use?
[24] The outcome of my own attempt to uphold “community standards” at a conference on Freud is one vivid instance of this phenomenon; see Crews, Follies 79-82.
[25] Thanks to Ranja Knöbl and
Joseph Carroll for their help in translating this paper.
[26] For a sketch of the field
see Eibl, “Naturwissenschaft.” See also the recent exchange in the Journal
of Literary Theory: Kelleter, “A Tale”; and Eibl, “On the Redskins”; and
see our review of The Literary Animal (Eibl and Mellmann, “Literatur.”).
[27] See Carroll, “Steven
Pinker’s Cheesecake”; for an indirect response see Pinker, “Toward” 169-73;
and, finally, the section on “The Adaptive Function of Literature” in the
target article.
[28] For a comprehensive
discussion of this distinction and the meaning of the word “adaptive” see Tooby
and Cosmides, “The Past.”
[29] See also Eibl, “Adaptationen.”
[30] See Groos, Die
Spiele der Menschen and Die Spiele der Tieren, referenced in Bühler,
Die geistige Entwicklung and Die Krise.
[31] See Schwender; and Mellmann,
Emotionalisierung, 42ff. and “Literatur.“
[32] For a survey on emotional
effects of literature see Mellmann, “Biologische Ansätze.”
[33] Tooby and Cosmides, “Does
Beauty Build?” 20-22. See also Cosmides and Tooby, “Consider.” Gehlen (Der
Mensch) had already conceived of the ‘unhinging’ of drive and action as the
origin of culture.
[34] Tooby and Cosmides, “Does
Beauty Build?” 20. See also Cosmides and Tooby, “Consider.” On the role of
language see Eibl, “Vergegenständlichung.”
[35] See C. Darwin, The Expression 166.
[36] Also see Boyd, “Evolutionary.”
[37] See for example the discussion in the Journal of Literary Theory: Eibl, “On the Redskins”; and Kelleter, “A Tale” and “The Polemical Animal.”
[38] In Tomasello et al., compare the account of sharing intentions as the basis of human communication, and see their references to Grice and to Sperber and Wilson.
[39] See Kelleter, “Tale”; Eibl, “Redskins”; Kelleter, “Polemic.”
[40] See Kelleter, “Polemic.”
[41] See Singer, Beobachter
120-143.
[42] “That unified explanation is
intrinsically satisfying,” Carroll claims. Even if this was true—which I
doubt—the question of adequate unification would remain.
[43] Also see Eibl and Mellmann’s highly critical review of The Literary Animal (“Literatur”).
[44]Darwin, however, unlike his predecessors and contemporaries, believed that distinct races were not distinct species. He understood that “race is not an empirically supported basis for biological differentiation in the genuinely scientific sense of the word” and that “‘the races of man are not sufficiently distinct to coexist without fusion’” (Niro 98-99).
[45]Carroll employs similar
language in his astute essay, “Human Universals and Literary Meaning: A Sociobiological
Critique of Pride and Prejudice, Villette, O Pioneers!, Anna
of the Five Towns, and Tess of the d’Urbervilles” (Literary
Darwinism 129-45).
[46] See Pinker, The Blank
Slate and How the Mind Works.
[47] See Biesele; Blurton Jones and Konner; Mithen, Thoughtful; and Rink 1875/1997. See also Scalise Sugiyama, “Food.”
[48] Hyman describes modern criticism as “the organized use of non-literary techniques and bodies of knowledge to obtain insights into literature,” and he says that “the bodies of knowledge of most usefulness to criticism are the social sciences” (Armed 3).
[49] For an account of how academic interpreters use scientific vocabularies to create non-scientific interpretations, see Seamon.
[50]Carlyle had this to say about Darwinism: “If true, it was nothing to be proud of, but rather a humiliating discovery, and the less said about it the better” (cited in Hyman, Tangled Bank). That doesn’t quite get things right, but the sentiment should not be ignored once Darwinism leaves the edifice of scientific achievement.
[51] See Flesch 205, note 6.