3. Sets, Classes, and Russell's Paradox

We will want to know how to do is how to construct sets. Unfortunately, as was discovered about 100 years ago, if you are not careful you get into trouble.

A Tentative Definition of Set Theory:

Axiom 1: Two sets are the same if and only if (write "iff") they have the same members.Symbolically,

$\QTR{Large}{X=Y}$ MATH .

Axiom 2: Let MATH be a proposition about mathematical objects then MATHtrue$\QTR{Large}{\}}$ is a set.

This sort of works! Try it. Look at the definitions of MATH and the open unit interval $\QTR{Large}{(}$0,1$\QTR{Large}{)}$ on Page 0.

Here is more interesting example. Let

MATH MATH MATH

MATH MATH MATH

MATH MATHx $\QTR{Large}{(}$x MATHy$\QTR{Large}{(\ }$y MATHx$\QTR{Large}{<}$y $\QTR{Large}{))}$

MATH MATHxMATHy $\QTR{Large}{(}$ x$\QTR{Large}{\in A}$ MATHy$\QTR{Large}{<}$x MATH yMATH

Let MATH

Then MATHtrue$\QTR{Large}{\}}$ is the set of Dedekind cuts.


Russell's Paradox (Discovered by Bertrand Russell in 1901):

Let MATH be the proposition "$\QTR{Large}{X}$ is a set that does not contain itself as a member." That is, MATH ,which can be written MATH. For almost any set that one thinks of MATHtrue. The set MATH, of integers is not an integer. However, by the Tentative Definition above, the set of all sets is a set so it is a member of itself.

MATHtrue$\QTR{Large}{\}}$

Now consider the set $\QTR{Large}{S}$ of all sets that do not contain themselves as a member, that is MATHtrue$\QTR{Large}{\}}$. The question is MATH? Of course, as in the case of the barber , if MATH then MATH and if MATH then MATH.


Mathematical Fallout:

In point of fact, in order to do mathematics we do want to be able to work with some version of 2. In particular, the "collection" of mathematical objects satisfying a particular list of axioms. For example, in this course we want to talk about "metric spaces" and we will need to do this in a way that avoids Russell's Paradox. As a first step in the next section we take a very brief look at Axiomatic Set Theory .