The Seven Bridges of Konigsberg Over the River Pregel:
Is there a route over the seven bridges that only traverses each bridge once?
Method 1:
Label the bridges
and
.
Try the
possibilities.
Method 2:
Consider the associated Graph:
and argue about traversal properties of nodes with an odd/even number of edges. In particular, in a "one-time traverse"
of a node with a even number of edges - a path both begins and ends there, or neither begins nor ends there .
of a node with a odd number of edges - a path must begin there or end there but not both.
Theorem:
There does not exist a rational number
such that
PROOF:.
Fundamental Lemma of Number
Theory: Let
be two integers. There exits unique integers
and
with
and
Note: Uniqueness follows from the
fact that
implies
Definition: Let
be two integers. The greatest common divisor of
and
is defined to be largest integer
such that
divides both
and
.
(
).
Since
divides both
and
, we can use induction to show that
exists. For that matter, since
one can compute
(very inefficiently!) by
trying all values, starting at
and ending at the least of
and
Examples:
.
Lemma: Suppose
then
.
PROOF:
In fact all of their common divisors are in common!
The Euclidean Algorithm for
computing :
Theorem( Extended Euclidean Algorithm): Let
There exists integers
and
, computable using the Euclidean Algorithm such that
PROOF:
(By induction)
If
the theorem is trivial so for simplicity assume that
.
Again if
divides
the theorem is trivial so assume
hence
If
divides
then
and
.
Otherwise
hence
and
or
again if
divides
we are done else......
Example- Compute
Computing the simple-minded way requires
long divisions. Divide
and
by
through
.
Now by the euclidean algorithm,
This admittedly is an easy example but we see that EA requires
long divisions to find
.
Lemma: Suppose
is prime (the only divisors are
and
).
Suppose
divides
then
divides
or
divides
.
PROOF: Suppose
does not divide
,
then
.
Thus there exists integers
and
, such that
Multiplying both sides of the equation by
gives
Finally, setting
we get an explicit divisor
In particular,
Proof that
there does not exist a rational number
such
that
Let
.
Assume
Given
a pair
we
know how to calculate
!
Multiplying, we have
.
Since
divides
we conclude from the lemma above (again a
calculation) that
for some
Hence
or
.
Hence as before
.
Thus
.
Theorem: Let f:[0,1]
[0,1]
be a continuous function then there exists an x such that f(x)
= x.
This is a consequence of the following
Intermediate Value Theorem: Let f:[0,1]
be
a continuous function. Let
f(0)
c
f(1).
Then there exists
a
[0,1]
such that f(a)
c.
To see how the first result follows from the second apply the intermediate
value theorem to g(x)=x-f(x).
One notes
that g(0)0
and g(1)
0
We will discuss this result in some detail, and in greater generality, in the second part of this course. The following brief discussion is simply meant to remind about the nature of the Real numbers and to continue to set the stage for our discussion of Set Theory. We begin with Dedekind's definition of the real numbers.
Definition: A Dedekind cut of the Rationals,
, is a subset
that satisfies these properties:
1.
is not empty.
2.
is not empty.
3.
contains no greatest element
4. For
if
and
,
then
.
the set of "Real Numbers" is defined to be the set of all Dedekind cuts of
Note that in the definition only the "order property" of
is used. We could, in fact, generalize the definition of Dedekind cuts by
simply replacing
with an appropriatley ordered set. One would then write something like
.
Examples:
Let
be a rational. Let
all
. We can consider
by observing that different rationals generate different Dedekind
cuts.(Exercise: Why?)
. Let
all
rationals
all positive rationals
such that
.
This gives us a "construction" of
Let
be a strictly increasing sequence of rational numbers that is bounded
above.
Define
all
such that there exists an
with
.
All bounded increasing sequences in
have limits in
(WHY?)
Note:
is
correct, since by assumption
we know
More generally, Let
.
Be an arbitrary set of Dedekind cuts that is bounded above, then
is a Dedekind cut. Bounded above simply means that there is some
such that
for any
.
Let
be
a finite set of Dedekind cuts, then
is a Dedekind cut.
Exercise:(to be turned in Wednesday Jan 26) Prove 4. and 5.
Solution for 4.:
We need check the the 4 properties of a Dedekind cut hold.
1. Since
,
2. Since
for any
,
, hence
3. Let
then
for
some
,
since
is
a cut there is some
with
.
But
implies
.
4. Is essentially the same argument.
Solution for 5.:
1. Choose
and let
since we only have a finite number of
this
makes sense. Since
and
for
all i.
for
all i. Hence
.
2. Since
and
we
can conclude that
.
3. Let
, choose
with
.
Now let
As
in 1. this exists. Check that
for all i, hence
and
4. Is immediate since if
,
and
,
then
for all i. hence
.
Exercise:(to be turned Wednesday Jan 26). Consider the set of positive infinite decimal fractions
where
0,1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9
and there does not exist an n such that
0
for
n
i
Show that there is a 1 to 1 order preserving map from set of positive infinite decimal fractions to the appropriate set of Real numbers.
Solution :
Let
to be more precise
Since the infinite decimal fractions is bounded above by 1,
we can apply 4. above to conclude
is a cut.
To see that distinct fractions result in distinct cuts, we begin by noting
that
and since the infinite decimal fraction does not end in a string of
0s, there is some m with
Assume
. Specifically, there is an n with
. One checks that this implies that for all n,
,
hence
. On the other hand since we can choose some s with
we have
. Thus
Observation :
Based on the examples above and the fact that there does not exist a rational
number
such that
we have
.
Definitions:
Real numbers can be compared. Let
and
be real numbers we define
if
.
One can also extend the rules of arithmetic so as to give the expected
properties of the Real numbers.
Comments:
After making the appropriate observations one might ask if the Dedekind
process could be repeated? In particular,
, itself, is a candidate for extension by Dedekind cuts. But,in fact, one can
show that the inclusion
(
)
is 1 to 1 and onto.
Thus, for example, one can revise Example
3. to show that all bounded increasing sequences in
have limits in
.
This is the heart of the Intermediate Value Theorem