In Mathematics, a Theory is a collection axioms and the collection of all statements that can be derived from them via logical inference.
A theory provides "concrete" model for a "mathematical concept." For example, Metric Spaces provide a model for sets with a concept of distance between members of the set.
A Theorem is a statement that can be derived from the axioms of a Theory.
Once we know the axioms, the theorems are determined. Of course, since proofs may be very hard to come by, finding the theorems for a given theory may be difficult.
In the other hand, the question as to whether a given theory provides a good model may not have a simple true or false answer. In particular, if a theory does not provide a good model, the theorems may be true but may not be particularly interesting or useful.
Indeed, this question, regarding Set Theory will occupy our attention for much of the Semester
Here is a list of familiar objects that will be of interest to us this semester.
The
Natural numbers {1,2,3,4,.....}
The
Integers {.....,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,4,.....}
The
Rational numbers
{
a
0,
b
1
or pairs a,b with
a
0
b
and
gcd(
a
,b)
1)}
The
Real numbers
0,1
All
Real numbers x such that
0
x
1.
More formally, {x
x
and
0
x
1}
The
Complex numbers
Many Others
First some logical notation:
The symbol
is
to be read "there exists."
The symbol
is
to be read "for every."
The symbol
is
to be read "not"
The symbol
is
to be read "implies"
The context that this notation will appear will be in the "language of Sets." In particular, whether or not a given property holds will depend on the Set that it belongs to.
Here are two examples, the second of which we will write in the more informal notation that we will use almost everywhere in these notes :
The first example, in increasingly formal language, is a
statement that is true
for
and
,
but not for
.
Try to
solve 3z
2.
For all x and y, if
x0
then there exists a z such that
xz
y.
x
y
if
x
0
then
z
xz
y
x
y
x
0
z
xz
y
Let f:[0,1]
[0,1]
be a continuous function then there exists an x such that
f(x)=x. You might remember the proof is just the
intermediate value theorem, using g(x)=x-f(x). One
notes that
g(0)
0
and
g(1)
0.The
statement is not true if you replace [0,1] by
.
Just choose f(x)=x+1.
Sections 1.1, 1.2, 1.4, and 1.5 cover what should be fairly familar territory in elementary set theory, unions, intersections, functions, equivalence relations, etc. (Assignment: Read this material and bring any questions to the next class)
We will want to look at products of sets. That is if
and
are sets
and
eg:
The
set of ordered pairs of Natural Numbers.
If
and
are sets, we will want to look a sets of functions (we will often use the term
"map") from
to
We use the notation
There is some important algebra here as well.
0.1 Definitions:
a. Fix
.
Suppose we are give a map
. We define a map
by the formula
for
b. Now fix
Suppose
we are give a map
. We define a map
by the formula
for
.
0.2 Lemma;
In the setting of 0.1
a. Suppose
is one to one then
is one to one.
b. Suppose
is onto then
is one to one.
Proof: Exercise(hint: immediate from the definitions)
0.3 Lemma:
a. Let
and
be sets. Let
and
be
the inclusions. Then, for any set
,
the map
is 1 to 1. If
and
are disjoint then it is also onto.
Note:
,
the ordered pair of maps
restricted
to
and
restricted
to
.
b. Let
and
be sets. Let
be the projection onto the "ith" axis. For any set
,
the map
is a 1 to 1 and onto.
Proof:
a.
Cutting through the notation, the proof is little more than observing
that any map
Is
uniquely determined by its values on
and
.
If
and
are disjoint then any pair of maps
can be combined to give a map on
. If not, only pairs
agreeing on
can be so combined, hence
is only 1 to 1.
b. is even more straight forward.