Science
Envy?
The simulacrum, thus constructed, does not render the world as it has found
it, and it is here
that structuralism is important. First of all, it manifests a new category of
the object, which is
neither the real nor the rational, but the functional, thereby joining a whole scientific complex
which is
being developed around information theory and research.
(Barthes, “The
Structuralist Activity,” 873b)
So while no one expects
literature itself to behave like a science, there is surely
no reason why criticism, as a systematic and organized study, should not be at
least partly a science.
Not a " pure" or "exact" science, perhaps, but these phrases form part of a
nineteenth-century cosmology that is no longer with us. Criticism deals with
the arts and may well be something of an art itself, but it does not follow
that it must be unsystematic. If it is to be
related to the sciences
too, it does not follow that it must be deprived of the graces of culture.
(Frye, “The Archetypes of Literature”,
693a)
Whatever
emendations the original formulation may now call for, everybody will agree
that the Saussurean principle of the arbitrary character of linguistic signs
was a prerequisite for the accession of linguistics to the scientific level.
The confusions
and platitudes which are the outcome of comparative mythology can be explained
by the fact that multidimensional frames of reference are often ignored or are
naively replaced by two- or three-dimensional ones. Indeed, progress in comparative mythology
depends largely on the cooperation of mathematicians who would undertake to
express in symbols multidimensional relations which cannot be handled
otherwise.
(Levi-Strauss,
“The Structural Study of Myth,” 861b, 867b)
By studying rites, customs, etc. As signs...I believe that we shall throw new light on the facts and point
up the need for including them in a science of semiology and explaining them by its laws.
(Saussure, Course in General Linguistics)