Some
critical remarks on the Parson’s Tale
and the Retractions
The Parson's Tale
seems a most inappropriate gloss for many of Chaucer's best poetic writings. It may
be unexceptionable in its theological doctrine, but in literary terms it is
ill-tempered, bad-mannered, pedantic, and joyless, and when it is used as a
gloss to the other tales it distempers them, fills them with ill humour, coats them with dust, and deprives them of
joy. I suspect that to reduce everything to the Parson's orthodox technicalities
is to miss the point of poetry. Surely it would be more sensible and humane to
use the rest of the tales as a gloss on the Parson's, counteracting its morbid
negatives with a few of their healthy affirmatives. After all, what Chaucer was
good at was not the formulation of doctrine on sin but the revelation of the marvellous variety of life in a world which, however
sinful, is the only world we've got, and one that can
mingle much delight with its inevitable corruption. The best medieval
literature does not necessarily have anything to do with sin, and it does just
what Chaucer does-offers joy to the reader. And that, despite the Parson, is no
sin.
·
E.T.
Donaldson, “Medieval Poetry and Medieval Sin,” in Speaking of Chaucer (Norton, 1970), 173
The Parson's Tale
is the last word of the Canterbury Tales; it is not the only word. Its
timelessness, paradoxically, has stood the test of time worse than those
distinctively fourteenth-century figures of the crusader Knight, the
well-mannered Prioress, and the Pardoner of St Mary Rouncesval.
Modern taste ranks the literary dazzle and the wit of the Nun's Priest above
the scholastic moralizing of the Parson. To Chaucer, both were valid. We live
in a world that allows for beast-fables and the Wife of Bath, but that has
little time for saints' lives and penitential treatises. The narrowing is ours,
not Chaucer's.
·
Helen
Cooper, Oxford Guides to Chaucer: the
Canterbury Tales, 407
This view, that Chaucer, at least from the moment he wrote the General
Prologue, intended to close this poem with something like ‘The
Parson's Tale,' will of course not please all readers. Quite
apart from those who are unwilling to look at him as anything other than a
cherished precursor of modern or post-modern sensibilities, some readers will find
it stupid to think that such an intelligent, sensitive, sympathetic artist as
Chaucer would "labor over fool's gold” and create characters and tales
full of life, realism, and pleasing artistry, only to revoke them at the end.
One could reply to this objection that perhaps, as he did in Troilus, Chaucer
deliberately involves his readers (and even more his Narrator, of course)
emotionally in the storytelling and in the world he creates in the tales, but
that at the end of the poem he as deliberately leads them to a higher plane and
thus effects in them a catharsis of mind and will. Fool' s
gold is what looks like gold in the eyes of fools, and I would maintain that,
for alert medieval readers or listeners, the poet embedded enough hints in the
early parts of the work to remind them that there is a higher reality behind
the phenomena that strike our senses. Isn't this artistic process and
structural progression, which plays with the reader's sense of appearance and
reality, just like what happens in Paradise Lost, where Satan with his
gigantic sense of freedom and self-determination eventually turns into a snake
with ashes in his mouth--even if some readers may continue to feel that he is
the real hero of the poem?
·
Siegfried
Wenzel, “The Parson’s Tale in Current Literary Studies,” in Raybin and Holley,
eds., Closure in the Canterbury Tales:
The Role of the Parson’s Tale (Kalamazoo, 2000)
Second, and the source of the greatest controversy, is the thematic
relation of the Parson's Tale to the rest of the Canterbury Tales. Among the
many discussions of this issue one can distinguish four positions: (1) the
moral absolutism of the Parson's Tale has been implicit throughout the tales,
guiding our judgment as we read them and now receiving its full expression and
authority; (2) the Parson's Tale provides a retrospective commentary on all
that has gone before, and our understanding of the tales should now (but only
now) be revised in the direction of its moral judgments; (3) the Parson's Tale
is itself subject to the comic and dramatic norms that govern the rest of the
Canterbury Tales and its absolutism is simply a last contribution to the
multifarious voices of the Canterbury conversation; (4) in both style and
substance the Parson's Tale is utterly foreign to the rest of the tales, its
significance is primarily biographical, and as a conclusion to the tales it
provides at best a pious gesture towards conventional standards of literary
seemliness.
*
* * * *
It is necessary, then, that the Parson's Tale should provide not a fulfillment to the tales but an
alternative, a complete and exclusive understanding of character, action, and
even language. But in concluding we must return to the paradox in which the tale
is grounded. If it cancels out rather than completes that which precedes, its
position at once enforces and weakens its authority. His tale takes its origin
in the very dramatic and realistic context which it will dismiss, and it is a
denial of the tale-telling game that in the first instance quits the Manciple. In sum, while the Parson has the last word he
must wait until last to say it, and although the transcendence of his message
is never in doubt he must wait until the imperfect and even immoral expressions
of merely verbal art have been passed in review. Chaucer and the pilgrims have
it both ways, but this should lead us to question neither their
nor Chaucer's sincerity. . . .Both the licentia and the medieval habit
of the repentance of old age encourage us to see the Parson's Tale as another instance of literary penance. This is a
penance that is neither perfunctory, as the care with which the tale is
composed suggests, nor unexpected. Rather it is a part of the fitting shape of
the Christian life, hardly a hypocritical volte-face but an inevitable and
gratifying process of change and fulfillment. 'Young devil, old saint' runs one
of the proverbs that express this conception, and its cynicism is tempered with
a benign assurance that each man's history is concluded with a reversal that is
both fulfillment and justification. It is in this radically linear awareness of
the range of human action in its response to divine requirements that we should
locate the paradox of a tale that can at once 'knytte
up al this feeste, and make
an ende.'
·
Lee Patterson, “The ‘Parson’s Tale’ and the Qutting of the ‘Canterbury Tales’,” Traditio 34 (1978): 333, 379-80
In the disclaimers
of The Canterbury Tales, the
Decameron and the Roman de la Rose, we
meet more than a good-humoured defense
against a minority puritanism. We meet a
genuine anxiety about the moral worth of
fiction. It applies particularly
to low fictions such as The Miller's Tale
or The Merchant's Tale, less
so to serious quasi-historical
or philosophical works such as The Knight's
Tale or The Clerk's Tale, not
at all to serious Christian works like The Man of Law's
Tale or The Second Nun's Tale. There is no difficulty in defending
these as morally elevating or, at
least, spiritually safe. The apology does
not extend to fabliaux; yet writing fabliaux
is a duty, as well as a pleasure,
in any anthology that aims at
literary inclusiveness and generic diversity.
And part of the pleasure
may stem from the writer's frisson of moral
unease. Chaucer does not ignore this tension.
He constructs from it the frame
of his collection.
* * * * *
The play that is
narrative, and materialism - for materialism, like narrative, is a love of
earthly things; and the penance that is perfect renunciation, death and the
celestial Jerusalem; the way to Canterbury, and the highway to truth: these are
the contradictory truths that exist, "like stages or stations of a
journey," in the sequence of the frame and structure of The Canterbury
Tales. Even for a Parson, sin has its
compensation--redemption; and in fragment I as we have it, the sin and its
retraction stand side by side just like the opposed values--fables and
truth, play and penance--of the Canterbury pilgrimage.
They stand side by side just as they do in The General
Prologue, which announces and foreshadows the pattern of the whole. The
matter can fairly be stated like this: the religious nature of pilgrimage is
conspicuously begged in The General Prologue and cries out for a
penitential correction. Since pilgrimage is connected with storytelling and
begins the frame, there is nothing strange in the idea that penitential
correction should end it.
·
David Lawton, “Chaucer’s Two Ways:
The Pilgrimage Frame of the Canterbury
Tales,” Studies in the Age of Chaucer
9 (1987): 26, 35-36
Chaucer's Retraction appears to
be anything but a single and unified utterance. Rather, it breaks into two sets
of assertions, assertions which are mutually exclusive. Chaucer's opening
benediction of his art is totally subverted by his closing malediction of his
art, and vice versa. His closing appeal to Christ, his mother, and all the
saints to save him from the sins of his written poems is entirely at odds with
his opening appeal to Christ and to the Bible as the author and authority of
the Christian truth and goodness in and of his poetry. Chaucer's readers--humanist,
exegete, or whatever--find themselves trapped willy-nilly in the middle of
Chaucer's final, paradoxical assessment of his art. If the humanist has been
wishing to suppress the Retraction as an unwanted supplement to the complete
body of Chaucer's poetry, he ironically will find within that supplement a
liberal aesthetic position that embraces, extends, and exaggerates his own. And
the exegete, who has been suppressing in various ways the supplement, the sweet
"solaas" of Chaucer's poetry, will find in
the Retraction a blessing of that supplement taken from the very Scriptural
authority which the exegete had himself been using to devalue secular writing.
On the other
hand, the exegete will find in the Retraction an aesthetic position so
conservative that it seems more a critical mockery than a sympathetic support
of his own. And the humanist will of course find in the Retraction not only a
position that so Scripturalizes all literature that
his own aesthetic seems much too secular, but a counterposition
that pretty much sends his aesthetic packing off in the direction of hell. No
wonder the Retraction has been read uncarefully even
by those who embrace it, for it is an embarrassment to all.
·
Peter Travis,
“Deconstructing Chaucer’s Retraction,” Exemplaria 3 (1991): 146-47